One commonly
employed cheap shot often directed at libertarians that supposedly goes a long way
towards instantly refuting all of libertarian thought is to claim that
libertarianism rests on the assumption that individuals are like isolated
atoms, just pursuing their own interests, not influencing or being influenced
by anyone else and not participating in social organizations. One gets the
sense that people who make such claims have never actually read anything by a
libertarian thinker or free-market economist. If they had, they would realize
that the vast societal system of exchanges and market prices, as well as the
division of labor which they enable and coordinate, are eminently social
phenomena that are central to libertarian thought and free-market economics.
Given this
popular confusion over what libertarian individualism means, in this post I
will discuss three important manifestations of libertarian individualism and
show why they in no way assume or imply anything about ‘isolated atomic individuals’.
1. Methodological Individualism:
Methodological
individualism is a key tenet of libertarian thought. It is by no means unique
to libertarianism; many other schools of thought adhere to it as well.
Methodological individualism consists of a belief in the simple statement that
it is only individuals who are capable of thinking, feeling, and acting, only
they can have desires and only they can attempt to find and employ suitable
means to attain those desires. Individuals can join together and interact with
other individuals for certain purposes, forming a society, but this society or
any of its subsets (such as nation, race, class, or family) is not capable of
having desires of its own or choosing means to pursue them. It is simply not
the case that society or one of its subsets has certain desires, and then
splits itself off into hive-minded individuals whose purposes are to attain
those desires for ‘society’.
It should be
clear that methodological individualism in no sense implies a belief in ‘atomic
individuals’. It recognizes that individuals can sometimes, individually,
decide to put the perceived interests of a collective (such as their family or
country) above their own narrowly-defined individual interests. But it is
always the individuals who are deciding that advancing the perceived interests
of a collective is their desire, and it is always the individuals who are
deciding upon and employing means to advance this desire. A collective is
incapable of doing these things, because at the end of the day it is just a conglomeration
of individuals. The clearest proof of this is the phenomena of immigration,
where a person decides or is forced by circumstances to leave one national
collective and join another one. How can collectives, who cannot think, feel,
decide, or act, possibly be a good basic unit of social analysis when
individuals have the power to leave them whenever they so choose?
2. Not much emphasis on any satisfaction that could be
derived from contemplating abstract characteristics of collectives:
This aspect
of libertarian individualism is not methodological, but partly normative and
partly based on psychological estimation. Most libertarians do not think that
much personal satisfaction can be derived from contemplating abstract
characteristics of collectives, separated from any individual goods which these
characteristics might be associated with. For example, most libertarians would
not agree with the statement: ‘I know that our country has enough military
capacity to defend itself against threats, but I derive great satisfaction from
knowing that my country is really strong militarily, hence I think that more
taxation in order to provide more tanks, fighter planes, and atomic bombs is
justified’. Or with the statement: ‘I accept that socialized health care will
result in a general decline in living standards due to the extra taxation, a
decline in the quality and quantity of available medical care, and relative
allocational chaos in its distribution, nevertheless, I derive great
satisfaction from knowing that my country is a ‘caring’ one, hence I think that
socialized health care should be implemented”.
In these two
statements, the individual is, unrealistically, admitting that his proposed
political measures are harmful to his and other people’s other interests, but
that the satisfaction derived from contemplating an abstract collective
characteristic such as a country being ‘strong’ or ‘caring’ trumps these
negative effects. This statement construction allows us to isolate the abstract
‘collective good’ from considerations of general material prosperity for
individuals.
Most libertarians would hold,
normatively, that they do not derive satisfaction from contemplating such
abstract collective characteristics and would estimate psychologically that
most people don’t actually desire much satisfaction from such things either.
Most people probably don’t derive that much satisfaction from contemplating
abstract collective characteristics, but support policies that libertarians
oppose because they disagree with the libertarian analysis of the effects of
the policies. Thus, most supporters of beefing up the military probably think
that more defense is actually needed or that military spending by government
will boost the economy in some way, and underestimate the damage caused by
taxation, inflation, and budget deficits. Similarly, most supporters of
socialized health care probably think that it is a more effective way of
distributing health care to citizens of a country than free-market health care,
and also underestimate the damage caused by taxation, inflation, and budget
deficits.
This aspect of libertarian
individualism is partly normative because it is certainly possible for people to gain great personal satisfaction from
contemplating abstract perceived characteristics of the collectives they belong
to, and to support political measures based on that subjective evaluation. Most
libertarians would not derive any satisfaction from such things though, and
estimate that the vast majority of people would not either, and hence do not
really factor it into their policy analyses. Whether you agree with this
assessment or not, holding this opinion in no way constitutes an assumption of
‘atomic individualism’.
3. Opposition to coercive collectives:
Another
charge commonly levied against libertarians, related to the charge of ‘atomic
individualism’, is that libertarians fail to realize that certain big projects
or achievements can only be accomplished by ‘a nation’ (a political collective
whose governing body has coercive powers considered legitimate), not by
individuals. It is said that only ‘a nation’ could have built the Hoover Dam, could
have sent a man to the moon, could have invented and developed the atomic bomb,
etc… An observer unacquainted with the facts, armed with this theory, could
just have easily maintained that only ‘a nation’ could develop the retailing
juggernaut with giant superstores and distribution centres located throughout
the world that is the contemporary Wal-Mart. However, he would be mistaken, for
in fact Wal-Mart was built by individuals voluntarily joining together to
pursue a common purpose.
Thus, it is
not big projects that only ‘a nation’ can tackle; it’s hard to get bigger than
Wal-Mart. However, the theory of public goods and economic externalities does
provide a rationale for why certain beneficial projects may not be undertaken
through voluntary cooperation. I discuss this theory, and what it does and does not imply, in this post: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/economic-externalities-raison-detre-for.html
For now,
suffice it to note that it is conceivable that certain beneficial projects
might not be undertaken through voluntary individual cooperation because a lot
of their benefits take the form of positive externalities, benefits that accrue
to other people not involved in the project for which the people involved in
the project are not remunerated monetarily for. Most economic goods involve
some positive externalities, but it is theoretically conceivable that economic
goods which involve a significant amount of positive externalities will either
not be produced or not produced in ‘optimal quantities’ through voluntary
interaction. The main problem with the theory is that it is impossible to
measure the existence or extent of positive externalities in an even marginally
reliable fashion, and that the common proposed solution, provision of the good
through government coercion, involves a host of other problems and may not even
solve the externalities problem in the first place.
The
libertarian response to the issue is generally to try and find innovative
free-market solutions to ‘internalize the externalities’ and point out
historical occasions where so-called ‘public goods’ exhibiting potentially
significant positive externalities have been provided voluntarily. Railroads
(James Hill’s Great Northern Railway: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Great_Northern_Railway_(U.S.)), roads (turnpikes in early American
history: http://www.uctc.net/research/papers/018.pdf), and municipal infrastructure (St
Louis Private Places: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Private_place), all classic examples of goods with
potentially significant positive externalities, have in the past been provided effectively
through voluntary individual associations.
Through
these examples, we see that what libertarians oppose is not individuals joining
together for some kind of collective action per se. Rather, libertarians tend
to oppose collectives that are established and maintained coercively, rather
than through voluntary agreement (unless you are a minarchist libertarian such
as myself, in which case it is permissible for the basic political society providing
law and order and defense against aggression to be maintained through
coercion). Even if the purpose of the coercively established and maintained
collective is to ‘solve an externalities problem’, this does not reduce the
general negative effects of coercive actions, and thus libertarians try to find
ways to solve any externalities problems through voluntary, free-market
arrangements.
Recognizing
the serious negative effects of extensive social arrangements based on coercion
and not accepting the positive externalities argument as a trump card
justification for coercive arrangements characterizes this aspect of
libertarian individualism. It by no means implies a rejection of the beneficial
nature of (voluntary) collective action nor a belief in ‘atomic
individualism’.
No comments:
Post a Comment