Sunday 20 April 2014

Critique of George Soros' 'The Crisis of Global Capitalism: Open Society Endangered

George Soros, The Crisis of Global Capitalism[1].

Chapter 1: Fallibility and Reflexivity

Soros: “Fallibility means that our understanding of the world in which we live is inherently imperfect. Reflexivity means that our thinking actively influences the events in which we participate and about which we think. Because there is always a divergence between reality and our understanding of it, the gap between the two, which I call the participants’ bias, is an important element in shaping the course of history. The concept of open society is based on the recognition of our fallibility. Nobody is in possession of the ultimate truth.” 4

Brian: Ok, fair enough so far.


Chapter 2: A Critique of Economics

Soros: “There is a prevailing belief that economic affairs are subject to irresistible natural laws comparable to the laws of physics. This belief is false.” 28

Brian: True, economic laws are nothing like the laws of physics. Most importantly, there are no constant, quantitative relations in economic affairs, while there are in physics. But qualitative economic laws that are almost certainly going to be true in every realistic scenario are valuable tools of cognition and should not be ignored. For instance, free-market economists say that if a maximum price control is set on a product that exceeds what the free-market price of that product would have been, shortages of that good will be created and its production will be discouraged. Shortages will be created because at the government-mandated price that is lower than the free-market price would have been; the quantity of the product demanded at that price will exceed the quantity of that product supplied at that price. Not everyone with a demand at that price will be satisfied; this being the definition of a shortage in economic terms. In addition, the production of that product will be discouraged by the imposition of the maximum price, other things equal. This is because at the mandated price, production of that good will most likely not be as profitable as the production of other goods whose prices have not been controlled by the government. Producers will most likely shift to the production of these other goods in their search for profits, and production of the price-controlled good will consequently be discouraged, thus exacerbating the initial shortage problem.

This economic law is a qualitative law. It does not say how severe of a shortage will be created, or how much production of the product will be discouraged by a maximum price control of a specified magnitude. It is thus unlike a physical law in this respect.

In addition, it is theoretically possible, though highly unlikely, for the predicted effect to fail to appear, due to countervailing, subjective forces. For instance, if enough consumers suddenly reduced their demand for the price controlled good as soon as the control was imposed, perhaps because they are ultra-loyal to their government or because they wanted to try to prove the economists wrong, than shortages might not develop. Similarly, if producers kept on producing the good in the same quantity even after the control was imposed, because they value the psychic satisfaction of pleasing their government or trying to prove the economists wrong more than the monetary profits that they will have to forego, than the production of the price-controlled good would not be discouraged. However, it is scarcely necessary to even finish describing such scenarios before dismissing them as near impossibilities, based on what we know about human nature and motivation in general.

Thus, while economic laws are not quantitatively-precise or absolute laws, they should not be ignored by policy makers lightly. A government that dismissed the reasoning of the economists and the millennia of negative experiences regarding maximum price controls could certainly try once again to impose a maximum price control without harmful effects, but they should not be surprised when their attempt fails dismally.   


Soros: “Economic and social events, unlike the events that preoccupy physicists and chemists, involve thinking participants. And thinking participants can change the rules of economic and social systems by virtue of their own ideas about these rules. The claims of economic theory to universal validity become untenable once this principle is properly understood. This is not just an intellectual curiosity. For if economic forces are not irresistible and if economic theories are not scientifically valid – and never can be – the entire ideology of market fundamentalism is undermined.” 29

Brian: Right, and as explained above, it is theoretically conceivable that a change in the thinking of the consumers could frustrate the predictions of the economists regarding the effects of imposing a maximum price control above the free-market price. But given what we know about humanity, in many cases this is just an ‘intellectual curiosity’. Would you really maintain that the theoretical teachings of free-market economics regarding the effects of imposing maximum price controls are worthless because of the incredibly slim possibility of a radical and unprecedented shift in consumer thinking preventing these effects from occurring? This would be a very impractical and pedantic attitude to take. Just because something isn’t absolutely, universally valid beyond a shadow of a doubt, doesn’t make it worthless. Quantum physicists have challenged the universal validity of Newtonian physics, but surely no one would describe Newtonian physics as worthless. Knowledge of ‘imperfect’ Newtonian physics is what enabled the construction of the machines and vehicles that have radically improved our lives over the past few centuries.


Soros: “When sellers know how much they are willing to supply at each price and buyers know how much they are willing to buy, all that needs to happen to achieve equilibrium is for the market to find the unique price that matches demand and supply. But what if price movements themselves change the willingness of buyers and sellers to trade their goods at given prices, for example, because they expect the price to rise further in the near future?” 37

Brian: Then the constellation of supply and demand will change and the equilibrium point will change? I don’t see what the problem here is. In Austrian economist Murray Rothbard’s explanation of the pricing process, he explicitly includes speculative factors as determinants of supply and demand. Just because supply and demand schedules are determined by complicated factors does not mean that the theory of pricing based on supply and demand considerations is flawed.


Chapter 3: Reflexivity in Financial Markets

Soros: “In the initial stage, the trend is not yet recognized. Then comes the period of acceleration when the trend is recognized and reinforced by the prevailing bias. A period of testing may intervene when prices suffer a setback. If the bias and trend are maintained, both emerge stronger than ever. Then comes the moment of truth when reality can no longer sustain the exaggerated expectations, followed by a twilight period when people continue to play the game although they no longer believe in it. Eventually a crossover point is reached when the trend turns down and the bias is reversed, which leads to a catastrophic acceleration in the opposite direction, commonly known as the crash.” 52

Soros: “Economic theory has actually promoted the tendency toward equilibrium by ignoring reflexivity and emphasizing the importance of fundamentals. By contrast, my argument leads to the conclusion that markets cannot be left to their own devices. Awareness of reflexivity only serves to increase instability unless the authorities are equally aware and intervene when the instability threatens to get out of hand.” 58

Brian: Your argument is overly simplistic. It blames herd-like investors for creating boom-bust financial cycles and looks to the government to act as a stabilizing force. This ignores the fact that government monetary and banking policies have been the prime contributors, throughout history, to financial instability and boom-bust cycles. Often, credit expansion, encouraged by the government, is what leads to the unrealistic expectations of investors in the first place. Credit expansion makes one investment sector artificially profitable through funnelling easy money heavily to it, thus creating a bubble. When credit expansion slows or is redirected, this bubble will burst as reality reasserts itself. Does the herd mentality of many investors exacerbate this kind of instability? Absolutely. But to downplay the government’s role in creating financial instability and to leave it the task of ‘stabilizing’ the financial markets is misleading and somewhat naïve.

Why should politicians care about financial stability? All they are interested in is having seemingly good economic conditions prevail during their short term in office. If they must create a bubble or a boom to accomplish this, at the expense of creating the conditions for a bust during the term of their successor, then so be it. Besides, even if government officials were interested in financial stability, how are they supposed to know if a given financial trend is an irrational speculative mania, or a beneficial adjustment to changed market conditions? You rightly pointed out that the assumption of perfect knowledge amongst market participants is incredibly unrealistic. So why should we assume that government officials have the perfect knowledge that they would need to ‘correct’ the market instead? How is that any more realistic?


Chapter 4: Reflexivity in History

Soros: “A transactional society undermines social values and loosens moral constraints. Social values express a concern for others. They imply that the individual belongs to a community, be it a family, a tribe, a nation, or humankind, whose interests must take precedence over the individual’s self-interests. But a transactional market economy is anything but a community. Everybody must look out for his or her own interests and moral scruples can become an encumbrance in a dog-eat-dog world. In a purely transactional society, people who are not weighed down by any consideration for others can move around more easily and are likely to come out ahead.” 75

Brian: One does not have to be a collectivist in order to be concerned about others. One can care about the interests of fellow family members, tribesmen, nationals, or other humans, without becoming a subordinate pawn of The Family, The Tribe, The Nation, or Humankind. In fact, often the supposed ‘interests’ of these collective entities are simply the selfish interests of the collective’s leaders in disguise.  

Soros says that people who don’t care about others are ‘likely to come out ahead’ in a purely transactional society (ie. a free-market society). Come out ahead, in terms of what? In what sense can we say that the person who only cares directly about himself is ‘ahead’ of the person who also cares about others in a free-market society? These people have different preferences, and in a free-market society they are free to pursue these different preferences, more or less successfully depending on how competent they are. The first person can spend his earned money directly on himself and attain gratification in that way, the second person can spend some of his earned money on others and attain some of his gratification in that manner. It is impossible for us to say which of these people will end up with a higher sense of psychic well-being, because one cannot compare psychic well-being interpersonally.

Perhaps Soros meant to say that selfish people will be able to accumulate more money, in their capacity as producers in a free-market society, than unselfish people. The trouble is that it is hard to judge which producer is being more ‘selfish’ than others in their market conduct. For instance, is it selfish of an efficient producer to set his prices lower than that of his less efficient competitors? One could say that the efficient producer’s actions show that he doesn’t care about the well-being of his competitors, but one could also say that the efficient producer’s actions show that he does care about the well-being of his customers, whom he is offering his goods at lower prices to. We can only really say that a producer is acting selfishly when he seeks an advantage for himself at the expense of both his competitors and the consumers. And yet, in a free-market economy, opportunities for doing so are relatively rare. It is in an interventionist economy where producers have all kinds of chances to seek special governmental privileges for themselves at the expense of their competitors and consumers.  Seekers of government subsidies, seekers of laws restricting entry into the industry or profession to one’s competitors, seekers of tariff protection, seekers of monopolistic franchises, etc… are all producers who can be said to be acting pretty selfishly, more so than producers acting on a purely free-market. In this light, it is the economy hampered by all kinds of government interventions that is more of a ‘dog-eat-dog-world’ than the pure free-market economy.  

Can’t free-market producers attempt to sell their customers shoddy products at over-inflated prices, and thus act selfishly in that regard? They can certainly try, but as any leader of an established business firm will tell you, the firm’s reputation for honesty and quality is one of its most important business assets, an asset that it is not wise to impair for the sake of fleeting short-term gains.
Thus, the common complaint that a free-market society will necessarily dominated by ‘selfishness’ and a ‘dog-eat-dog mentality’ is in many respects faulty.       


Chapter 6: The Global Capitalist System

Soros: “A key feature of fundamentalist beliefs is that they rely on either/or judgments. If a proposition is wrong, its opposite is claimed to be right. This logical incoherence lies at the heart of market fundamentalism. State intervention in the economy has always produced some negative results. This has been true not only of central planning but also of the welfare state and of Keynesian demand management. From this banal observation, market fundamentalists jump to a totally illogical conclusion: If state intervention is faulty, free markets must be perfect. Therefore the state must not be allowed to intervene in the economy. It hardly needs pointing out that the logic of this argument is faulty.” 127-128

Soros: “Market fundamentalism plays a crucial role in the global capitalist system. It provides the ideology that not only motivates many of the most successful participants but also drives policy. In its absence, we would not be justified in talking about a capitalist regime. Market fundamentalism came to dominate policy around 1980, when Ronald Reagan and Margaret Thatcher came to power more or less simultaneously.” 128

Brian: I can’t think of even one thinker who has ever said that the free-market is ‘perfect’. Even anarcho-capitalist thinkers, who believe that the State shouldn’t exist at all and that the free-market is better than state intervention in all areas, don’t claim that the free-market is ‘perfect’. They just argue that the costs of government intervention always exceed the benefits, not that the free-market is ‘perfect’ by some mysterious standard of perfection. As for the neoclassical economists whom Soros is referring to, they tend to advocate for government control of the monetary and banking system and for heavy government involvement in the education system and in the provision of so-called ‘public goods’. These hardly seem like the political positions of people who think that ‘free markets must be perfect’ in all areas and that the state should never intervene in the economy.        

The fact is that, in order to take a complete political position, one must specify how much government intervention, of what nature, one is willing to support in each area of the economy. If one comes to the conclusion that in most areas of the economy, government intervention is counterproductive, and thus that only very limited government interventions in specified sectors should be supported, this is not a mark of being a ‘market fundamentalist’. As I wrote in an earlier post:

“If someone thinks and can persuade others that the science of economics demonstrates that measure A leads to ends B and C, while measure B leads to ends D and E, and this person values ends B and C higher than he values ends D and E, then it doesn’t matter how many times these judgements favour the free-market, while shunning government economic intervention. To simply proclaim that someone’s scientific and value judgements cannot be correct because taken together, they constitute an ‘extreme’ position on the free-market versus government economic control spectrum, is to abdicate all responsibility for actually analyzing these scientific and value judgements yourself. In fact, who is more ‘extreme’, the person who makes a separate scientific and value judgement on each issue as they come up, or the person who dismisses the need for such judgements by proclaiming that the ‘moderate’ position must be right? The latter would seem to be the attitude closer to religious dogma, and the former closer to the attitudes of science.”[2] 

This idea of ‘market fundamentalists’ ruling the modern world is an indefensible interpretation of history. Government’s role in the US economy did not shrink significantly under Reagan, and has not shrunk since. Government spending as a percent of GDP in the US now and in the 1980s was significantly higher than it was in the 1960s. This is hardly a sign of a shift in policy orientation towards ‘market fundamentalism’. This pervasive myth impedes clarity of thought on modern political issues, and thus should be discarded forthwith.   

Chapter 8: How to Prevent Collapse

Soros: “Whatever currency regime prevails, it is bound to be flawed. Freely fluctuating currency rates are inherently unstable because of trend-following speculation; moreover the instability is cumulative because trend-following speculation tends to grow in importance over time. On the other hand, fixed exchange rate regimes are dangerous because break-downs can be catastrophic. The Asian crisis is a case in point. I often compare currency arrangements with matrimonial arrangements: Whatever regime prevails, its opposite looks more attractive.” 184

Soros: “A major experiment is currently under way in Europe: the creation of a single currency. It is based on the belief, which I share, that in the long run you cannot have a common market without a common currency. I believe, however, that the design of the euro is flawed because in the long run you cannot have a common currency without a common fiscal policy, including some kind of centralized tax collection or tax redistribution.” 184-185

Brian: How about an international gold standard? Currencies wouldn’t be unstable with regards to one another because there would only be one currency for the whole world: gold. This would facilitate international trade and international financial transactions and would eliminate the pervasive risk of currency fluctuations that will always exist under a national paper money system. With one currency for the whole world, one immune to hyperinflationary destruction, there would be no question of ‘catastrophic’ currency break-downs. Thus, an international gold standard would avoid the problems that Soros identifies with floating rate and fixed rate national paper money systems, while providing all kinds of other important monetary benefits as well.

If we want the world to be a common market, than a common currency would greatly help, as Soros himself recognizes. Gold served as just such a currency during the 19th and early 20th centuries. Why could it not do so again? Soros thinks that countries with a common currency must have a common fiscal policy. This is only true if central banks are empowered to print units of the currency in order to facilitate the excessive deficit spending of profligate governments within the currency zone, as the European Central Bank does. In that case, a common monetary policy results in resources being redistributed from countries with more responsible governments to governments with more profligate governments. This is clearly an unsustainable arrangement, replete with perverse incentives. Under a real international gold standard, there would be no central bank with the power to ‘print’ gold and use it to help fund the activities of profligate governments. Thus, there is really no need for the countries using gold as their currency to adopt a common fiscal policy.    


Brian’s General Comments:  While Soros’ book does present some interesting ideas and interpretations, it is frustratingly vague on its concrete policy recommendations. Soros champions the idea of an ‘Open Society’, but his main definition of such a society is one based on the idea of human fallibility. This nebulous definition is never really fleshed out in the form of concrete policy recommendations, with the exception of some tentative suggestions for how to better regulate international financial markets.

Soros, armed with his concept of fallibility, argues that both the market mechanism and the democratic political process are flawed. Well, of course they are, nothing created by imperfect humans is going to be perfect, and what is perfection anyway? But the pressing political question is: how much should the government intervene in each area of the economy? Evasive answers about human fallibility and institutional imperfection will not do. The question must be answered in a straightforward manner, using all of our relevant social scientific knowledge, and in light of all of our personal value judgements.    



 





[1] George Soros, The Crisis of Global Capitalism: Open Society Endangered (New York: PublicAffairs, 1998).
[2] Brian David, Thinking Like a Libertarian, Part 1, Tip #22: Beware the Tyranny of Moderation.

Sunday 13 April 2014

Critique of Thomas Piketty, 'Capital in the 21st Century'

Thomas Piketty, Capital in the 21st Century[1].

Part One: Income and Capital

Chapter 1: Income and Output

Piketty: “In this book, capital is defined as the sum total of nonhuman assets that can be owned and exchanged on some market. Capital includes all forms of real property (including residential real estate) as well as financial and professional capital (plants, infrastructure, machinery, patents, and so on) used by firms and government agencies.”

Brian: This broad definition of capital is satisfactory when considering it from the standpoint of ‘distribution’, which (unfortunately) Piketty does almost exclusively throughout the book. However, when considering capital from the standpoint of production, which Piketty (unfortunately) neglects to do, narrower, more sub-divided definitions are necessary. Piketty’s definition of capital should then be divided into: 1. Productivity-increasing, reproducible, investment capital goods (tools, equipment, machines, buildings, etc…). 2. The non-reproducible elements of real estate (location, ground land, natural resources). 3. Consumer capital (durable consumer goods, residential real estate and housing, consumption loans.) 4. Government permissions and privileges (patents, copyrights, licenses, permits, etc…). All of these play very different roles in the production process, and should not all be lumped together. More on this later.    


Piketty:Generally speaking, the global income distribution is more unequal than the output distribution, because the countries with the highest per capita output are also more likely to own part of the capital of other countries and therefore to receive a positive flow of income from capital originating in countries with a lower level of per capita output. In other words, the rich countries are doubly wealthy: they both produce more at home and invest more abroad, so that their national income per head is greater than their output per head. The opposite is true for poor countries.”

Brian: No doubt. But there is no injustice here: the poor countries would be even poorer if they weren’t helped out by the investments of foreign capital.


Chapter Two: Growth: Illusions and Realities

Piketty: “In the short run, the problem of “relative prices” can be neglected, and it is reasonable to assume that the indices of “average” prices published by government agencies allow us to correctly gauge changes in purchasing power. In the long run, however, relative prices shift dramatically, as does the composition of the typical consumer’s basket of goods, owing largely to the advent of new goods and services, so that average price indices fail to give an accurate picture of the changes that have taken place, no matter how sophisticated the techniques used by the statisticians to process the many thousands of prices they monitor and to correct for improvements in product quality.”

Brian: I wouldn’t be so optimistic about short-run price indices, but I appreciate your skepticism about long-run ones.


Piketty: “In fact, neither the economic liberalization that began around 1980 nor the state interventionism that began in 1945 deserves such praise or blame. France, Germany, and Japan would very likely have caught up with Britain and the United States following their collapse of 1914–1945 regardless of what policies they had adopted (I say this with only slight exaggeration). The most one can say is that state intervention did no harm. Similarly, once these countries had attained the global technological frontier, it is hardly surprising that they ceased to grow more rapidly than Britain and the United States or that growth rates in all of these wealthy countries more or less equalized, as Figure 2.3shows (I will come back to this). Broadly speaking, the US and British policies of economic liberalization appear to have had little effect on this simple reality, since they neither increased growth nor decreased it.”

Brian: You say it with great exaggeration in fact. Did the communist countries ‘catch up’ to the US as rapidly as the western European countries after the war? Of course not, they stagnated in misery because of grossly inappropriate government policies.

I don’t know what you mean when you say that ‘state interventionism’ began in 1945. Germany and Japan were extremely economically liberal in the post-war period compared to their fascist recent pasts. France was relatively economically liberal itself during the post-war and De Gaulle years, it turned to more socialist policies later on. 

There was no significant ‘economic liberalization’ in the 1980s, it was mainly rhetorical. In fact, the 80s and the decades that followed were far more statist (government spending and regulations played a greater role in the economy) than the post-war years in the US, France, Germany, and Japan. Only in Britain can we say that some economic liberalization really occurred under Thatcher, when compared to the socialistic post-war period, although its extent is grossly exaggerated by most commentators.

Finally, technology is by no means the overriding factor determining economic growth. Technological knowledge is useless without the capital to implement it, without the skilled labor force to operate it, and without the economic freedom to exploit it effectively.  


Part Two: The Dynamics of the Capital/Income Ratio

Chapter 3: The Metamorphoses of Capital

Piketty:  “More precisely, remember that national capital, which is shown in Figures 3.1 and 3.2, is defined as the sum of private capital and public capital. Government debt, which is an asset for the private sector and a liability for the public sector, therefore nets out to zero (if each country owns its own government debt).”

Brian: ‘Private capital’ and ‘public capital’ are two entirely separate things and should not be lumped into an aggregate figure. In reality, government debt diverts capital from private uses to ‘public’ uses. These ‘public’ uses might not actually constitute productive investments, they might just be consumption or counter-productive (such as war financing or regulatory bureaucracy financing) instead. In any meaningful measure of capital’s role in the economy, government debt certainly does not ‘net out to zero’.

While we’re on the subject of over-aggregation, it is a bit dubious to include residential real estate in ‘national capital’ as you do. Residential real estate is a consumption good, not a production good. When free-market economists say that capital accumulation leads to economic growth, they have in mind capital that is invested for the purpose of making more money in the future, achieved through making a production process more efficient in the future. Durable consumer goods such as residential real estate and random government expenditures are not of this character, so to aggregate them with real productive capital is misleading for many purposes.


Piketty: “National capital (or wealth) is the sum of public capital and private capital. Public capital is the difference between the assets and liabilities of the state (including all public agencies), and private capital is of course the difference between the assets and liabilities of private individuals.”

Brian: While this definition is okay for private capital, it is misleading for public capital. The fact is that the bigger the government’s balance sheet, the more of the economy’s capital stock it is directing. If the government pays for 1 trillion dollars worth of assets by issuing 1 trillion dollars worth of bonds to the private sector, this action is not a wash as it is in Piketty’s definitions, but is very significant. With this action, the government now has the power to commission, to shape, and to direct 1 trillion dollars worth of capital assets. Yes, in a certain nominal sense it is the government’s private creditors who ‘own’ these assets, but this 1 trillion dollars of capital is firmly devoted to the governmental sector, rather than to the private sector. If the government hadn’t purchased the assets by issuing the bonds, these 1 trillion dollars of capital would have been invested in the private sector. Some of it would have landed in durable consumer goods investments such as residential real estate, but a great portion of it would have turned into private productive investment capital, which would have contributed significantly to increasing economic productivity, real wages, and growth. The government’s action thus changes the character of the capital significantly, and can’t be ignored by any thorough analysis.


Piketty: “Second, it is also quite clear that, all things considered, this very high level of public debt served the interests of the lenders and their descendants quite well, at least when compared with what would have happened if the British monarchy had financed its expenditures by making them pay taxes. From the standpoint of people with the means to lend to the government, it is obviously far more advantageous to lend to the state and receive interest on the loan for decades than to pay taxes without compensation. Furthermore, the fact that the government’s deficits increased the overall demand for private wealth inevitably increased the return on that wealth, thereby serving the interests of those whose prosperity depended on the return on their investment in government bonds.”

Brian: Yes, all true. It should be added though that the high level of public debt did not serve the interests, and in fact went against the interests, of everyone else. For it served to divert private capital from productive private investments to unproductive public consumption (in this case, destructive wars). 


Chapter 4: From Old Europe to the New World

Piketty: “In the long run, the capital/income ratio β is related in a simple and transparent way to the savings rate s and the growth rate g according to the following formula:
β = s / g
For example, if s = 12% and g = 2%, then β = s / g = 600%.2
In other words, if a country saves 12 percent of its national income every year, and the rate of growth of its national income is 2 percent per year, then in the long run the capital/income ratio will be equal to 600 percent: the country will have accumulated capital worth six years of national income.
This formula, which can be regarded as the second fundamental law of capitalism, reflects an obvious but important point: a country that saves a lot and grows slowly will over the long run accumulate an enormous stock of capital (relative to its income), which can in turn have a significant effect on the social structure and distribution of wealth.
Let me put it another way: in a quasi-stagnant society, wealth accumulated in the past will inevitably acquire disproportionate importance.


Brian: This formula is not very helpful because the savings rate is not a static rate at all. People aren’t just going to keep accumulating savings in a low growth economy at the same rate indefinitely. Rather, each person will decide how much in savings they want, and when they have reached their desired level, they will stop saving and start consuming all of their income. Some people (for example, people who have retired) will probably have a negative savings rate, while others (for example, young people saving for their first home) will probably have a higher than average savings rate. But if enough savings in general have been accumulated already, than these kinds of opposing actions will simply result in a transfer of savings from one person to another, not in a positive overall savings rate.

This brings us to another important point. Piketty says that “in a quasi-stagnant society, wealth accumulated in the past will inevitably acquire disproportionate importance”. Maybe so, but it is by no means certain that in such a society the people or the descendants of the people who have accumulated this wealth in the past will acquire a disproportionate economic importance. Individual people and families gain and lose wealth all the time, quasi-stagnant society or not. This important dynamic is obscured by the focus on ‘national’ wealth and income statistics. No investment is absolutely safe, and the safer it is, the lower the return it will generally make, while those taking more risks will tend to make a higher return. Even land and housing, once thought to be ‘stable’ and ‘permanent’ investments, have become quite volatile and risky investments in the modern, rapidly changing world. Those making a low return on their ‘safe’ investments will probably, if they want to maintain a high standard of living, have to consume some of their capital eventually, while thrifty people making a high return on their ‘risky’ investments will be able to accumulate additional capital.             
 

Chapter 6: The Capital-Labor Split in the Twenty-First Century

Piketty: “The principal conclusion that emerges from my estimates is the following. In both France and Britain, from the eighteenth century to the twenty-first, the pure return on capital has oscillated around a central value of 4–5 percent a year, or more generally in an interval from 3–6 percent a year. There has been no pronounced long-term trend either upward or downward. The pure return rose significantly above 6 percent following the massive destruction of property and numerous shocks to capital in the two world wars but subsequently returned fairly rapidly to the lower levels observed in the past. It is possible, however, that the pure return on capital has decreased slightly over the very long run: it often exceeded 4–5 percent in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, whereas in the early twenty-first century it seems to be approaching 3–4 percent as the capital/income ratio returns to the high levels observed in the past.”

Brian: These figures make perfect sense. Generally speaking, the more capital is flowing around the economy seeking returns, the lower these returns will be (higher supply means, other things equal, a lower price (rate of return)).


Piketty:First, the returns indicated in Figures 6.3 and 6.4 are pretax returns. In other words, they are the returns that capital would earn if there were no taxes on capital or income. In Part Four I will consider the role such taxes have played in the past and may play in the future as fiscal competition between states increases. At this stage, let me say simply that fiscal pressure was virtually nonexistent in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. It was sharply higher in the twentieth century and remains higher today, so that the average after-tax return on capital has decreased much more over the long run than the average pretax return.”

Brian: The after-tax return is a more important figure than the pre-tax return. It allows proper comparison between past rates and present rates, which the pre-tax return does not. And, it represents the return that investors are willing to accept in order to supply the amount of savings that they do. If the taxes on capital were repealed, users of capital would pay less in order to induce the same amount of investment by owners of capital. After-tax returns also seem more relevant for computing ‘shares of national income’, as in what sense can we say that ‘capital’ has a ‘share of national income’ based on its pre-tax rate of return? Owners of capital do not receive this ‘share’, the government does.


Piketty:The interesting question is therefore not whether the marginal productivity of capital decreases when the stock of capital increases (this is obvious) but rather how fast it decreases. In particular, the central question is how much the return on capital r decreases (assuming that it is equal to the marginal productivity of capital) when the capital/income ratio β increases. Two cases are possible. If the return on capital r falls more than proportionately when the capital/income ratio β increases (for example, if r decreases by more than half when β is doubled), then the share of capital income in national income α = r × β decreases when β increases. In other words, the decrease in the return on capital more than compensates for the increase in the capital/income ratio. Conversely, if the return r falls less than proportionately when β increases (for example, if r decreases by less than half when β is doubled), then capital’s share α = r × β increases when β increases. In that case, the effect of the decreased return on capital is simply to cushion and moderate the increase in the capital share compared to the increase in the capital/income ratio.”

Brian: True, but the thing which we must keep in mind is that the more private productive investment capital is invested effectively, the more productive the economy will tend to be. Thus, whether ‘capital’s share’ of ‘national income’ increases or decreases as more capital is accumulated, this ‘national income’, in terms of real goods that both laborers and capitals can consume with their ‘shares’, will consist of more consumable goods than it would have if there were less capital accumulated. This is something that we should always keep in mind. How large a slice of the pie we get at a given time matters less and less the faster the pie itself is growing over time. 


Part Three: The Structure Of Inequality

Chapter 9: Inequality of Labor Income

Piketty: “First, as shown in the previous chapter, the increase in wage inequality in the United States is due mainly to increased pay at the very top end of the distribution: the top 1 percent and even more the top 0.1 percent. If we look at the entire top decile, we find that “the 9 percent” have progressed more rapidly than the average worker but not nearly at the same rate as “the 1 percent.” Concretely, those making between $100,000 and $200,000 a year have seen their pay increase only slightly more rapidly than the average, whereas those making more than $500,000 a year have seen their remuneration literally explode (and those above $1 million a year have risen even more rapidly).11 This very sharp discontinuity at the top income levels is a problem for the theory of marginal productivity: when we look at the changes in the skill levels of different groups in the income distribution, it is hard to see any discontinuity between “the 9 percent” and “the 1 percent,” regardless of what criteria we use: years of education, selectivity of educational institution, or professional experience. One would expect a theory based on “objective” measures of skill and productivity to show relatively uniform pay increases within the top decile, or at any rate increases within different subgroups much closer to one another than the widely divergent increases we observe in practice.”

Brian: Let me start by saying that I don’t think the rapid increase in top-earner wages in the US can be explained entirely by free-market forces. Increasingly, established firms rely more and more on government privileges and connections rather than on superior efficiency. They can thus afford to become more indolent and bureaucratic, and are more likely to acquiesce in paying their top managers unnecessarily large salaries. Also, the existence of Chapter 11 bankruptcy rules and restrictions on hostile takeovers make top managers more powerful within the corporate form, which gives them more bargaining power when it comes to setting their salaries. These things can and should be corrected by changes in government policy.

Nevertheless, the marginal productivity theory of wage remuneration of free-market economics can help explain the existence of very large salaries for top managers. Piketty, incorrectly, maintains that the theory is based on “objective” measures of skill and productivity. Actually, it is based on subjective, speculative anticipations on the part of the people responsible for hiring the top managers. They determine, not unreasonably, that a person who seems to have the right intangible personality traits and a solid track record as a top manager would make a great CEO. They determine, also not unreasonably, that a great CEO, given the importance of the role, could make the firm a lot more profitable than just a good CEO. For a large firm, this difference in profitability could be on the order of hundreds of millions of dollars. As such, they will be perfectly willing to pay the great CEO tens of millions more in salary than the good CEO; the great CEO is worth the price in marginal terms. When it comes to CEOs, choosing someone who isn’t ideal for the job based on differences of even millions of dollars in salary is not generally a good policy. 
 

Chapter 10: Inequality of Capital Ownership

Piketty: “Under these assumptions, we find that the return on capital, net of taxes (and losses), fell to 1–1.5 percent in the period 1913–1950, which was less than the rate of growth. This novel situation continued in the period 1950–2012 owing to the exceptionally high growth rate. Ultimately, we find that in the twentieth century, both fiscal and nonfiscal shocks created a situation in which, for the first time in history, the net return on capital was less than the growth rate. A concatenation of circumstances (wartime destruction, progressive tax policies made possible by the shocks of 1914–1945, and exceptional growth during the three decades following the end of World War II) thus created a historically unprecedented situation, which lasted for nearly a century. All signs are, however, that it is about to end. If fiscal competition proceeds to its logical conclusion—which it may—the gap between r (rate of return on capital) and g (growth rate of the economy) will return at some point in the twenty-first century to a level close to what it was in the nineteenth century (see Figure 10.10). If the average tax rate on capital stays at around 30 percent, which is by no means certain, the net rate of return on capital will most likely rise to a level significantly above the growth rate, at least if the central scenario turns out to be correct.”

Brian: Stop it right there. Let’s say that users of capital currently pay 5% on average to use the capital, but that with taxes the owners of capital only receive a 3% rate of return. If the taxes on capital income are now repealed or reduced, then the rate of return on capital will indeed suddenly increase, from 3% to 5%. But, as a result, the supply of savings and investment will soon increase, given this higher return. All those users of capital who were willing and able to pay (implicitly or explicitly) 5% for the use of the capital were able to get access to all of the capital that they needed at that rate. But, with the tax, a 3% rate of return is obviously enough to bring in enough of a supply of capital to meet these needs, as owners of capital don’t care about their pre-tax rate of return, only their after-tax rate of return. With the tax repealed, the users of capital continue paying 5%, but the owners of capital now receive all of that 5% themselves. But this higher rate will invariably result in more savings and investment being supplied to the market. The rate of return cannot remain at 5%, given this new supply. The users of capital willing and able to pay 5% were already doing so. In order to bring forth more users of capital to accommodate the now larger supply of the owners of capital, the rate of return must fall. How much it will fall depends on many complicated factors, but fall it will.        


Piketty: “Let me now turn to the consequences of r > g for the dynamics of the wealth distribution. The fact that the return on capital is distinctly and persistently greater than the growth rate is a powerful force for a more unequal distribution of wealth. For example, if g = 1 percent and r = 5 percent, wealthy individuals have to reinvest only one-fifth of their annual capital income to ensure that their capital will grow faster than average income.”


Brian: Yes, if average r times average % of r saved is > g, than capital will grow faster than average income. If g= 2 percent and r= 4 percent, then the average % of r saved to make the capital grow faster than national income must be over 50%. Few wealthy people save over 50% of their capital income though, as, assuming they have a sufficiently large capital, they generally use most of their capital income for consumption purposes. Add in all of the people who, for whatever reason, deem it to be time to start consuming some of their capital, and the average percent of capital income saved should be well-below 50% (in the US in 2005, the overall personal savings rate was actually negative!). A growth rate of 2 percent and an average rate of return of 4 percent are not at all unrealistic, and would probably be achieved or surpassed in a true free-market economy.

In addition though, why all the worry about capital growing faster than average income? This just means that capital will be accumulated at a good pace, which will lead to higher growth rates and lower rates of return on capital in the near future. Piketty seems to treat g as a largely independent variable that cannot really be changed. But it can be changed, and the primary way of changing it positively is through more rapid capital accumulation and through more economic freedom.

       
Chapter 11: Merit and Inheritance in the Long Run

Piketty:Whenever the rate of return on capital is significantly and durably higher than the growth rate of the economy, it is all but inevitable that inheritance (of fortunes accumulated in the past) predominates over saving (wealth accumulated in the present). In strict logic, it could be otherwise, but the forces pushing in this direction are extremely powerful. The inequality r > g in one sense implies that the past tends to devour the future: wealth originating in the past automatically grows more rapidly, even without labor, than wealth stemming from work, which can be saved. Almost inevitably, this tends to give lasting, disproportionate importance to inequalities created in the past, and therefore to inheritance.”

Brian: This seems dubious for a number of reasons. Incompetent heirs will tend to earn significantly lower rates of return on their capital than the average. This is because they will probably hire portfolio managers to manage their investments, whose fees will be deducted from any return made, and because they will probably prefer safer investments with a lower rate of return to more risky, entrepreneurial investments with a higher rate of return. Moreover, they will probably have become accustomed to a high standard of living, a standard of living which they will probably not want to impair in order to increase their fortune. As such, they will probably use most of their capital income for consumption purposes, and may even dip into the fortune itself and consume some of the capital at times. These forces will result in a given inherited fortune becoming less and less significant in the economy as time goes by, the opposite of what Piketty predicts.


Piketty: “If the twenty-first century turns out to be a time of low (demographic and economic) growth and high return on capital (in a context of heightened international competition for capital resources), or at any rate in countries where these conditions hold true, inheritance will therefore probably again be as important as it was in the nineteenth century. An evolution in this direction is already apparent in France and a number of other European countries, where growth has already slowed considerably in recent decades. For the moment it is less prominent in the United States, essentially because demographic growth there is higher than in Europe. But if growth ultimately slows more or less everywhere in the coming century, as the median demographic forecasts by the United Nations (corroborated by other economic forecasts) suggest it will, then inheritance will probably take on increased importance throughout the world.”

Brian: Forget population growth, economic growth can occur just fine with or without it. In fact, if population growth became excessive, economic growth would probably start to suffer. UN demographic forecasts are largely irrelevant in this discussion.

Yes, it is possible that if the twenty-first century features low economic growth and high returns on capital, then it is possible that inheritance might take on increased importance throughout the world, although this is by no means certain, given the nature of incompetent heirs discussed above. But is it an immutable law of nature that the twenty-first century will be one with low economic growth and high returns on capital? Of course not, economic phenomena are always subject to human control and modification. So the question is: what can we humans do to avoid this fate?

Piketty has already hinted at his proposed ‘solution’: lower the after-tax rate of return through taxes on capital income and lower the significance of inherited wealth through inheritance taxes. If you are a fan of egalitarianism, this could help ‘solve’ the so-called ‘problem’ of ‘distribution’. But ‘distribution’ is not the only factor in economics: before there is ‘distribution’ there must first be production. The more is produced, or the faster the economy grows, the more there is for any ‘distribution’.

As such, I would like to propose a solution that not only takes ‘distribution’ into account, but also takes production and economic growth into account. Piketty worries about the gap between the rate of return on capital and the economic growth rate. He doesn’t seem to think that there’s anything that can be done about the economic growth rate, so he wants to reduce the rate of return on capital through taxation. But I say that there is something that can be done about the economic growth rate. With more capital accumulation and more economic freedom, there is no reason why the economic growth rate cannot increase. At the same time, with more capital accumulation, the rate of return will fall due to the increased supply of capital seeking uses. Thus, in this way, not only is Piketty’s gap reduced, thus mitigating his ‘distribution’ problem, but production and economic growth are increased, thus resulting in more economic goods to ‘distribute’ in the first place. This positive solution is thus infinitely better than Piketty’s negative ‘solution’.    


Piketty:Figure 11.1 represents the evolution of the annual inheritance flow in France from 1820 to 2010.2 Two facts stand out clearly. First, the inheritance flow accounts for 20–25 percent of annual income every year in the nineteenth century, with a slight upward trend toward the end of the century. This is an extremely high flow, as I will show later, and it reflects the fact that nearly all of the capital stock came from inheritance.”

Brian: Inheritance flow as a percent of national income is interesting, but it fails to reveal who exactly is doing the bequeathing. Let us return to the incompetent heirs we discussed above. A rich father passes a large fortune to his incompetent heir. This is recorded as an inheritance flow. The incompetent heir squanders half of the fortune before the end of his life, and passes a reduced fortune to his heir. What happened to the portion of the fortune that the incompetent heir squandered? A brilliant and energetic entrepreneur, who was about the same age as the incompetent heir, accumulated, through his very profitable business activities and high rates of saving out of these high profits, a fortune equal in size to the half of the large fortune that the incompetent heir squandered. This entrepreneur dies at the same time as the incompetent heir, and passes his fortune down to his own heir. Both halves of the original fortune, now as part of two separate estates, are recorded as an inheritance flow. If, instead of this, the incompetent heir hadn’t been incompetent and had managed to maintain his father’s fortune intact until his death, then the inheritance flow statistics would look the same.

The point is that large inheritance flows as a percent of national income do not necessarily imply the existence of an ever-rich aristocracy of great dynastic families. Yes, large inheritance flows mean that certain heirs will hit it lucky, but they do not mean that the same economic inequalities established in the past will remain in perpetuity.

There is, in fact, some good evidence that socio-economic mobility is still alive and well, in the US at least, contrary to Piketty’s implications. Free-market economist Gary Galles summarizes a 2007 US Treasury study called Income Mobility in the U.S from 1996 to 2005 as follows:
The Treasury found that those with the very highest incomes in 1996 — the top 1/100 of 1 percent — had their incomes halved by 2005 (missed by using statistical classes, because such decreases move people out of the top category). That hardly shows a class of rich growing ever richer at the expense of other classes.
Other income categories revealed a similar story. From 1996 to 2005, the incomes of those originally in the top 1 percent and 5 percent both declined; the incomes of those originally in the top 20 percent increased 10 percent; but those originally in the bottom 20 percent saw a 91 percent increase in income (missed by using statistical classes, because such increases move people out of the lowest 20 percent)”
Gary Galles, “The Rich Aren’t Dispossessing the Rest”, Mises.org, https://mises.org/daily/5799/The-Rich-Arent-Dispossessing-the-Rest

Piketty:the share of inherited wealth in total wealth has grown steadily since the 1970s. Inherited wealth once again accounted for the majority of wealth in the 1980s, and according to the latest available figures it represents roughly two-thirds of private capital in France in 2010, compared with barely one-third of capital accumulated from savings.”

Brian: Firstly, one-third of private wealth accumulated through savings is certainly a big enough proportion for the kind of gradual shifts of wealth to different estates described above. It still does not imply that the economy is dominated by aristocratic, dynastic families.

Secondly, high progressive income tax rates and corporate tax rates make it much more difficult to accumulate wealth through high incomes and savings. Reduce these tax rates and wealth accumulated through savings will increase in relative economic importance.      

Thirdly, for those who appreciates productive investment capital’s vital, positive role in the economy, these statistics reinforce the inadvisability of raising inheritance taxes, something which Piketty will no doubt recommend later on in the book. For the higher inheritance taxes are, the less of an incentive people will have to maintain their fortune past their expected time of death. In the extreme case, if inheritance taxes were 100%, than people would plan to consume all of their wealth before they died. Unless this capital consumption were offset by increased capital accumulation through saving elsewhere in the economy (and there is no reason to believe that the savings rate would increase if the inheritance tax were raised), than the economy would become less capital intensive, which would tend to make it less productive and would result in lower real wages for the workers who are now deprived of the productivity-increasing tools that they used to work with. Given that inherited wealth constitutes over two-thirds of private wealth in the economy (in France at least), any policy which significantly reduced the incentive to maintain this wealth and invest it productively would be economically catastrophic.     

Piketty: “In France today, there are certainly fewer very large estates—estates of 30 million or even 5 or 10 million euros are less common—than in the nineteenth century. But since the total volume of inherited wealth has almost regained its previous level, it follows that there are many more substantial and even fairly large inheritances: 200,000, 500,000, 1 million, or even 2 million euros. Such bequests, though much too small to allow the beneficiaries to give up all thought of a career and live on the interest, are nevertheless substantial amounts, especially when compared with what much of the population earns over the course of a working lifetime. In other words, we have moved from a society with a small number of very wealthy rentiers to one with a much larger number of less wealthy rentiers: a society of petits rentiers if you will.”

Brian: Exactly the point I was making; though there are still large total inheritance flows, there are few aristocratic, eternal, dynastic families. This seems a lot less dire than Piketty’s earlier rhetoric about the past tending to ‘devour’ the future. So a bunch of lucky people get a significant one-shot bonus when their parents die, so what? Is it reasonable, out of envy for these people, to undermine our economies through destructive taxation policies in order to take away this advantage? Personally, I don’t think it is.

  
Piketty:in a democracy, the professed equality of rights of all citizens contrasts sharply with the very real inequality of living conditions, and in order to overcome this contradiction it is vital to make sure that social inequalities derive from rational and universal principles rather than arbitrary contingencies. Inequalities must therefore be just and useful to all, at least in the realm of discourse and as far as possible in reality as well.”

Brian: Firstly, the idea that every inhabitant of a given region should have an equal vote when it comes to electing certain officials of the government of that region (political democracy) is entirely separate from the idea that every such inhabitant should have equal economic standards of living (economic egalitarianism). Inequality of wealth and incomes in a democratic country is not a ‘contradiction’ of democracy.

Secondly, the inequalities as a result of inheritances are useful to most people in the country, contrary to popular belief. As I discussed above, the institution of inheritance results in more productive investment capital being accumulated than would be accumulated in its absence, which in turn benefits almost everybody in the world, especially the residents of the country where the inheritance is accumulated.    


Piketty: “In any case, the unreliability of the US sources makes it very difficult to study the historical evolution of inheritance flows in the United States with any precision.”

Brian: So you will confine your conclusions to France then? I somehow doubt it.


Chapter 12: Global Inequality of Wealth in the Twenty-First Century

Piketty: “The problem is simply that the entrepreneurial argument cannot justify all inequalities of wealth, no matter how extreme. The inequality r > g, combined with the inequality of returns on capital as a function of initial wealth, can lead to excessive and lasting concentration of capital: no matter how justified inequalities of wealth may be initially, fortunes can grow and perpetuate themselves beyond all reasonable limits and beyond any possible rational justification in terms of social utility.”

Brian: Didn’t you just point out in the previous chapter how, in France at least, wealth was divided amongst a number of petits rentiers, rather than a few gigantic rentiers? This hardly seems consistent with fortunes growing and perpetuating themselves “beyond all reasonable limits”.

Also, again, you don’t really appreciate the social utility represented by capital accumulation. It is not just ‘the entrepreneurial argument’ that is used to justify all inequalities of wealth by free-market economists, it is also ‘the capitalist argument’ which is as important, if not more important, than the entrepreneurial argument.       


Part 4: Regulating Capital In The Twenty-First Century

Chapter 13: A Social State for the Twenty-First Century

Piketty: “The simplest way to measure the change in the government’s role in the economy and society is to look at the total amount of taxes relative to national income.”

Brian: No, government spending as a percent of GDP is a much better measure. Whether financed by taxation or financed by massive budget deficits and the inflation that enables them, the more the government spends for its activities, the greater role it has in the economy. Looking only at taxes relative to national income will lead to underestimating the relative role of the government in an era of large government budget deficits, and will lead to overestimating the relative role of the government in an era of small or non-existent government budget deficits.    


Piketty: “No major movement or important political force seriously envisions a return to a world in which only 10 or 20 percent of national income would go to taxes and government would be pared down to its regalian functions.”

Brian: So what? Maybe all ‘major movements’ and ‘important political forces’ are deluded. Personally, I think that 20 percent of national income going to taxes is already pretty hefty, 10 percent would probably be more than sufficient. At any rate, majority vote is not the arbiter of truth or reasonableness.


Piketty: “In the abstract, it should be possible to combine the advantages of decentralization with those of equal access by providing universities with substantial publicly financed incentives. In some respects this is what public health insurance systems do: producers (doctors and hospitals) are granted a certain independence, but the cost of care is a collective responsibility, thus ensuring that patients have equal access to the system. One could do the same thing with universities and students.”

Brian: No, even in the abstract, it is not possible. Chronic shortages of the things that customers want, lack of innovation, and horrible customer service result whenever a ‘public health insurance system’ is implemented. This is not some kind of strange coincidence: it is what invariably happens whenever profit-motive-based decision-making is replaced by bureaucratic decision-making. The same features are present in the public education system up to secondary school, and would become even more prevalent than they currently are in the higher education system the more control government sought over these institutions.


Chapter 14: Rethinking the Progressive Income Tax

Piketty: “Taxation is not a technical matter. It is preeminently a political and philosophical issue, perhaps the most important of all political issues. Without taxes, society has no common destiny, and collective action is impossible.”

Brian: You seem to be employing a strange definition of ‘collective action’. The Oxford English Dictionary defines the adjective ‘collective’ as: “Done by people acting as a group”[2]. Thus, collective action means: ‘An action performed by people acting as a group’.

Are taxes necessary to enable people to perform actions as a group? Of course not! People can contribute money to voluntary associations such as clubs or charities in order to enable these groups to act. People can contribute money as shareholders to a corporation to enable it to act as a unit with all of the share capital at its disposal. These are a few good examples of voluntary collective action, something that is very widespread throughout society. Thus, perhaps what Piketty meant to say was: ‘Without taxes, coerced collective action is impossible’. If he said that, then I would agree entirely with the statement. Coerced collective action is of course impossible if the organization that supposedly ‘represents’ the group (the government in this case) cannot collect money, through the threat of coercive force, from its ‘members’. In fact, in this correct form, the statement is almost a tautology.

“Without taxes, society has no common destiny”. This statement is very obscure. Members of the same group can never have a ‘common destiny’: the collective actions of the group will necessarily affect each constituent individual in a different way. No matter what a government of a geographical area does, it will not affect each of its individual citizens in the same way, and hence is incapable of creating a ‘common destiny’ for them. If a government declares war on another country and decides to use conscription to advance the war effort, do the poor conscript and the President doing the declaring really share a ‘common destiny’ because of this action? One is shipped off, against his will, to fight foreigners in muddy trenches, while the other can sit around in a comfortable office back home issuing commands. This doesn’t seem like a ‘common destiny’ to me. Similar considerations apply to every government policy, from regulatory policy, to taxation policy, to monetary policy. Everyone in ‘society’ is affected differently by these policies: there is no ‘common destiny’ involved.

Am I perhaps wasting too much time criticizing Piketty’s rhetorical statements? I don’t think so. Feel-good rhetorical statements such as these that, upon examination, don’t actually make sense, can mislead readers into accepting questionable doctrines which they otherwise wouldn’t have.
  

Piketty: “When a government taxes a certain level of income or inheritance at a rate of 70 or 80 percent, the primary goal is obviously not to raise additional revenue (because these very high brackets never yield much). It is rather to put an end to such incomes and large estates, which lawmakers have for one reason or another come to regard as socially unacceptable and economically unproductive—or if not to end them, then at least to make it extremely costly to sustain them and strongly discourage their perpetuation. Yet there is no absolute prohibition or expropriation. The progressive tax is thus a relatively liberal method for reducing inequality, in the sense that free competition and private property are respected while private incentives are modified in potentially radical ways, but always according to rules thrashed out in democratic debate. The progressive tax thus represents an ideal compromise between social justice and individual freedom. It is no accident that the United States and Britain, which throughout their histories have shown themselves to value individual liberty highly, adopted more progressive tax systems than many other countries.”

Brian: Free competition and private property are respected by confiscatory tax rates, these being a ‘relatively liberal method for reducing inequality’?! Sorry, but this is simply not true. Let us say that the democratically-elected government of a country is Catholic, and to discourage Protestantism, declares that any money voluntarily given to support Protestant churches will be taxed at a 90% rate before they can be spent by the church. ‘For one reason or another’ (ie. because they are Catholic fanatics), the lawmakers of this country have come to regard Protestantism as ‘socially unacceptable’ and ‘economically unproductive’. There is, of course, no ‘absolute prohibition’ on Protestantism, or ‘expropriation’ of Protestants and their churches; this government is ‘relatively liberal’ after all. ‘Free competition’ between churches is still allowed, and the ‘private property’ of Protestants is respected, it’s just that ‘private incentives are modified in potentially radical ways, but always according to rules thrashed out in democratic debate’. Of course, after this law is passed, most of the Protestant churches are forced to close their doors or to radically downsize their activities. But, that is just the result of the modified ‘private incentives’. Would Piketty regard this hypothetical case as ‘relatively liberal’? I truly hope not.

Free competition and private property are only truly respected when people are secure in the ownership of the resources that they have produced, earned, or purchased, and when they are free to use these resources to engage in the non-aggressively-violent commercial or personal activities of their choice, unhampered by physical force and coercion or the threat thereof. Confiscatory taxation puts a great barrier between resources earned in the market and secure ownership of those resources. It also puts great barriers between resources owned and their use for the activities of the owner’s choice. True private ownership of property implies the right to dispose of that property as the owner sees fit, without being molested by wielders of physical force. Confiscatory taxation is entirely incompatible with this.
      

Piketty: “A rate of 80 percent applied to incomes above $500,000 or $1 million a year would not bring the government much in the way of revenue, because it would quickly fulfill its objective: to drastically reduce remuneration at this level but without reducing the productivity of the US economy, so that pay would rise at lower levels.”

Brian: So essentially, we are talking about an effective price cap on top executive pay of about $1 million, and so we should analyze it as such. In general terms, price caps below the free-market level result in two main negative effects: the production effect and the allocation effect. The production effect is when production of the good with the price cap imposed on it is curtailed because the price cap makes its production artificially unprofitable for producers, who turn to the more profitable production of goods without price caps instead. In the case of top executive pay, I agree with Piketty that this effect will not really apply. I doubt that people will refuse to acquire the necessary skills and attributes to become top executives just because of the $1 million price cap.

The allocation effect is when the more urgent demanders of the good cannot outbid the less urgent demanders of the good due to the existence of the price cap. If a maximum price is set on gasoline, the trucker delivering vital food supplies to cities is prohibited from outbidding the family who plans to drive to a camp site for the weekend for the scarce supply of gasoline. This effect will apply to the case of top executive pay. Large companies will essentially be prohibited from outbidding smaller companies for the scarce supply of world class top executive talent. In general, leading larger companies is probably more stressful and less pleasant than leading smaller companies, thus the price cap on executive pay could well result in too many top executives opting for spots in smaller, less important companies, where their unique skills aren’t as value productive as they would be in the larger, more important companies.

Also, why would this price cap result in pay ‘rising at lower levels’? The marginal productivity of workers lower on the pay scale will not magically increase because the top executives are getting paid less, so why would their pay rise? Assuming that Piketty is correct and that paying any salary past $1 million is pure waste from the firm’s perspective, the result would be an increase in the relevant firms’ profits in the short-run. Their production, sales, and sale prices would remain unchanged, they would just have less labor expense, so the amount saved would be added right on to profits. In the long-run, if the firm’s profits were elevated above the general market rate (taking relevant risk premiums into account) as a result of smaller executive salaries, then more competition or potential competition would be attracted to the industry, which would result in a tendency for the firm’s profits to be competed down to the general market rate. This would result in lower prices for consumers in general, not in specific pay increases at lower levels of the wage scale.            

Chapter 15: A Global Tax on Capital

Piketty: “Here, the important point to keep in mind is that the capital tax I am proposing is a progressive annual tax on global wealth. The largest fortunes are to be taxed more heavily, and all types of assets are to be included: real estate, financial assets, and business assets—no exceptions.”

Brian: Ok, so accumulation is to be discouraged and penalized through taxation. On the other hand, present consumption will be encouraged. People will consume more and save less: the economy, following people in general, will become more present-oriented and less future-oriented. The result will be lower productivity as generally, the more time-consuming, complex, and multi-staged a production process, the more product per unit of labor it can produce. The Industrial Revolution was based on the replacement of less time-consuming, more simple, and less multi-staged production processes with more time-consuming, complex, and multi-staged production processes. A reversal of the Industrial Revolution would do just the opposite. I would prefer not to reverse the Industrial Revolution, but to advance it, so I must oppose policies which penalize capital accumulation.
  

Piketty: “Nevertheless, another classic argument in favor of a capital tax should not be neglected. It relies on a logic of incentives. The basic idea is that a tax on capital is an incentive to seek the best possible return on one’s capital stock. Concretely, a tax of 1 or 2 percent on wealth is relatively light for an entrepreneur who manages to earn 10 percent a year on her capital. By contrast, it is quite heavy for a person who is content to park her wealth in investments returning at most 2 or 3 percent a year. According to this logic, the purpose of the tax on capital is thus to force people who use their wealth inefficiently to sell assets in order to pay their taxes, thus ensuring that those assets wind up in the hands of more dynamic investors.”

Brian: If people are forced to sell their assets in order to pay their taxes, there are other, more important effects besides the same assets winding up ‘in the hands of more dynamic investors’. In order to accommodate a higher volume of these kinds of sales, the price of the relevant capital assets will have to fall, unless the demand for them goes up. Where would this additional demand come from? Would private individuals suddenly start saving and investing more because a capital tax is levied? Of course not, just the opposite in fact. Only if the government, who now has additional purchasing-power due to the levying of the capital tax, demanded the assets could their price be prevented from falling. And yet, governments don’t tend to demand the same kinds of things as private investors do, to put the case mildly. The government spends most of its funds for consumption purposes, and when it ‘invests’, it tends to do so in an inefficient manner, in a way that is governed by very different principles than private investment (bureaucratic and political principles rather than profit-seeking principles). So the private capital assets being sold to pay the tax would fall in price, while the assets that the government will demand with their tax money will rise in price. Economic actors will adjust accordingly to this new situation. Thus, what would happen is that the economy would become less capital-intensive in terms of private capital, and government would take a bigger role in the economy instead.

Also, the primary incentive introduced by a capital tax will be an incentive to not save and invest in the first place, but rather to consume instead. Saving and investment requires postponing gratification and worrying about preserving one’s accumulated wealth. With the rewards of doing so reduced, there will be less of an incentive to engage in this process, and more of an incentive to just consume in the present. As I explained above, this is bad for general economic productivity.
      

Chapter 16: The Question of the Public Debt

Piketty: “A much more satisfactory way of reducing the public debt is to levy an exceptional tax on private capital. For example, a flat tax of 15 percent on private wealth would yield nearly a year’s worth of national income and thus allow for immediate reimbursement of all outstanding public debt.”

Brian: What? How is this ‘satisfactory’ at all? Rob holders of assets other than government debt in order to repay the holders of government debt. Why should the holders of government debt be so privileged? Why should people whose ‘investment’ is dependent upon the ability of governments to levy large taxes in the future be privileged over people who genuinely seek to invest in wealth-generating, private commercial ventures? It seems clear to me that the latter are more praiseworthy and useful investors than the former.


Piketty: “First, it is always very difficult to predict the ultimate incidence of a debt repudiation, even a partial one—that is, it is difficult to know who will actually bear the cost. Complete or partial default on the public debt is sometimes tried in situations of extreme overindebtedness, as in Greece in 2011–2012. Bondholders are forced to accept a “haircut” (as the jargon has it): the value of government bonds held by banks and other creditors is reduced by 10–20 percent or perhaps even more. The problem is that if one applies a measure of this sort on a large scale—for example, all of Europe and not just Greece (which accounts for just 2 percent of European GDP)—it is likely to trigger a banking panic and a wave of bankruptcies. Depending on which banks are holding various types of bonds, as well as on the structure of their balance sheets, the identity of their creditors, the households that have invested their savings in these various institutions, the nature of those investments, and so on, one can end up with quite different final incidences, which cannot be accurately predicted in advance.”

Brian: True, but this is only because banks are run on a fractional-reserve basis. This wouldn’t be a problem if banks were on a 100% reserve basis. I outlined a plan to deal with the government debt, without absolute repudiation, to stabilize the currency, and to bring the banks to a 100% reserve basis, all at the same time, in a previous post: (http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/five-political-imperatives-1-monetary.html). I think that this solution would be infinitely better than Piketty’s draconian 15% levy on private capital.  


Piketty: “To be sure, one argument in favor of inflation remains: compared with a capital tax, which, like any other tax, inevitably deprives people of resources they would have spent usefully (for consumption or investment), inflation (at least in its idealized form) primarily penalizes people who do not know what to do with their money, namely, those who have kept too much cash in their bank account or stuffed into their mattress. It spares those who have already spent everything or invested everything in real economic assets (real estate or business capital), and, better still, it spares those who are in debt (inflation reduces nominal debt, which enables the indebted to get back on their feet more quickly and make new investments).”

Brian: No, it’s really not that simple. In an inflation, prices do not all rise at the same time. Inflation benefits those who are exposed to the new money flowing through the economy earlier, while penalizing those who are only exposed to the new money flowing through the economy later. The prime beneficiary of inflation is, obviously, the person doing the money printing himself (usually the government, could be a counterfeiter). Then, as that new money flows through the economy, those whose selling prices rise before their buying prices are benefitted, at the expense of those whose buying prices rise before their selling prices. What this means is that those that have the closest economic relations with the money printer (favoured financial institutions, defense contractors, receivers of government subsidies in the case of the government as money printer) will benefit at the expense of those whose economic relations are the most distant with the money printer (those holding a lot of cash, those on fixed incomes, people in areas of the economy remote from the needs of the money printer). Inflation is a wild and arbitrary redistributive force that certainly does deprive people of resources they would have spent usefully, just in a more subtle manner than outright taxation.

Also, what’s wrong with people who want to hold a lot of cash? What act of villainy are they really committing? The fact that they are holding cash does not withdraw productive resources from the universe: it just means that prices in general will fall from what they otherwise would have been and business will carry on as usual at these lower prices. Besides, cash reserves can be an important force for financial stability. If companies kept higher cash reserves, they would be more protected against bankruptcy during financial crises. What’s wrong with that? You would think this would be something to be applauded after the scarring 2008 financial crisis.


Piketty: “If the global stock of gold was static but global output increased, the price level had to fall (since the same money stock now had to support a larger volume of commercial exchange). In practice this was a source of considerable difficulty.” (Note 17)

Note 17: “An often-cited historical example is the slight deflation (decrease of prices and wages) seen in the industrialized countries in the late nineteenth century. This deflation was resented by both employers and workers, who seemed to want to wait until other prices and wages fell before accepting decreases in the prices and wages that affected them directly. This resistance to wage and price adjustments is sometimes referred to as “nominal rigidity.” The most important argument in favor of low but positive inflation (typically 2 percent) is that it allows for easier adjustment of relative wages and prices than zero or negative inflation.

Brian: Hold on, why would wages have to fall if global output increased? Global output can only increase if the productivity per unit of labor goes up. But if the productivity of a kind of labor goes up, then the employer can afford to, and will have to if they don’t want that labor to be bid away from them, pay the worker higher real wages. For your ‘average’ worker, this will mean that if the global stock of gold is static but global output increases, their nominal wages, in gold, will remain unchanged, while the purchasing-power of each unit of gold will increase with the extra goods on the market, thus increasing their real wages. The only reason why nominal wages would have to fall, proportionate to the increase in global output, for the ‘average’ worker, given a static money supply, would be if the supply of labor increased as dramatically as the supply of goods, that is, if there was constant population growth at a fairly rapid rate. And yet, population growth has only a weak correlation with increase in the production of economic goods, and once a certain standard of living has been achieved, it tends to have a negative correlation (for example, the low birth rates in wealthy western countries in the present-day).

Of course, if the economic progress that resulted in the increase in global output served to make a worker’s skills less important, than their nominal wages would probably fall. But this would be counterbalanced by the nominal wage rise of those workers whose skills have become more important as a result of the economic progress. Having to occasionally reduce the nominal wages (perhaps not even the real wages) of workers whose skills have become less important as a result of economic progress hardly seems like too big of a price to pay to avoid all of the many evils of inflation (arbitrary redistribution, discouragement of thrift, catalyst of the business cycle, falsification of economic (monetary) calculation, risk of a hyperinflationary destruction of the currency, etc..).  


Piketty: “The fact is that all economists—monetarists, Keynesians, and neoclassicals—together with all other observers, regardless of their political stripe, have agreed that central banks ought to act as lenders of last resort and do whatever is necessary to avoid financial collapse and a deflationary spiral.”

Brian: Except for Austrian economists and libertarians, but I guess they are too ‘radical’ to be even worthy of a mention by Piketty. Austrian economists point out that central banking and the fractional-reserve banking system that it encourages are what create an unstable financial system in the first place, and are what make sudden monetary contractions possible. Inflation via credit expansion, according to Austrian Business Cycle Theory, is the primary cause of the boom-bust business cycle, and fractional-reserve banking serves to make the banking and financial system vulnerable to major economic shocks. With a gold standard and 100% reserve banking, banks wouldn’t need ‘lenders of last resort’, and sudden economic crises would become much less common and severe than they are now. There would be no major monetary contractions (deflations) because the money supply is the gold supply, so unless people suddenly decided to shoot their gold bars into space, there is no reason why the money supply should contract. By contrast, under a fractional-reserve system, the lending policies and financial situations of the commercial banks can result in either sudden expansions or sudden contractions of the money supply.

In this light, the contention that it is a good idea that central banks act as lenders of last resort in a financial system characterized by boom-bust cycles and fractional-reserve banking, promoted by the institution of central banking and fiat money itself, takes on a different character. It is akin to a thug shooting you in the leg, and then asking you whether you would like him to try to patch you up with his first aid kit or not. Given that you have already been shot in the leg, agreeing to the first aid treatment is probably a good strategy. Of course, it would have been better if you hadn’t been shot in the leg in the first place, because then the first aid treatment wouldn’t have been necessary. Central banks shoot their economies in the leg, and then they try to treat the wound with their ‘lender of last resort’ first aid kits. The first aid is perhaps appreciated, but it would be much better if the central banks hadn’t existed in the first place.    


Piketty: “Central banks are powerful because they can redistribute wealth very quickly and, in theory, as extensively as they wish. If necessary, a central bank can create as many billions as it wants in seconds and credit all that cash to the account of a company or government in need. In an emergency (such as a financial panic, war, or natural disaster), this ability to create money immediately in unlimited amounts is an invaluable attribute. No tax authority can move that quickly to levy a tax: it is necessary first to establish a taxable base, set rates, pass a law, collect the tax, forestall possible challenges, and so on. If this were the only way to resolve a financial crisis, all the banks in the world would already be bankrupt. Rapid execution is the principal strength of the monetary authorities.”

Brian: The ability to rapidly plunder the economy, without any democratic deliberation or oversight, is an ‘invaluable attribute’? Perhaps to the government, the central bankers, and their crony friends, but it is certainly not ‘invaluable’ to me. In fact, I would value the opportunity to destroy this authoritarian monstrosity very highly. It’s hard to see how this enormous power wielded by central banks fits in with democratic theory, or with the idea of ‘government by laws, not by men’. I’m sure the apologists could come up with something, but for those armed only with common sense, a central bank is pretty clearly an authoritarian and arbitrary institution.   


Piketty: “How did Europe come to create—for the first time in human history on such a vast scale—a currency without a state?”

Brian: Um, it didn’t? Gold and silver were currencies ‘without a state’ that lasted for millennia, and they were far more internationally accepted than the Euro.


  







[1] Thomas Piketty, Capital In The Twenty-First Century, transled by Arthur Goldhammer (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2014).
[2] http://www.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/english/collective