(Note: Before reading this critique, I recommend that you
read my critique of John Stuart Mill’s Utilitarianism,
which can be found here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2014/01/critique-of-john-stuart-mills.html)
Peter Singer’s Practical
Ethics[1].
Chapter 1: About Ethics
Singer: “From an ethical point of view, the
fact that it is I who benefit from, say, a more equal distribution of income
and you who lose by it, is irrelevant. Ethics requires us to go beyond ‘I’ and
‘you’ to the universal law, the universalizable judgment, the standpoint of the
impartial spectator or ideal observer, or whatever we choose to call it.” 12
Brian: Ok, but why care about the opinions
of ghostly ‘impartial spectators’ or ‘ideal observers’? The only good reason to
do so is if it is in your own, personal interest, which in many cases it is
when humans are living in a society together, as I explained in the preface to
my critique of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism.
Chapter 2: Equality and
Its Implications
Singer: “There is a popular belief that if
we did not pay people a lot of money to be doctors or university professors,
they would not undertake the studies required to achieve these positions. I do
not know what evidence there is in support of this assumption, but it seems to
me highly dubious. My own salary is considerably higher than the salaries of
the people employed by the university to mow the lawns and keep the grounds
clean, but if our salaries were identical I would still not want to swap
positions with them – although their jobs are a lot more pleasant than some
lowly paid work. Nor do I believe that my doctor would jump at a chance to
change places with his receptionist if their salaries did not differ.” 42
Brian: So many things are wrong with this
passage. First, if all jobs were paid the same, people would decide their
career paths based on non-monetary, psychic considerations alone. In other
words, people would decide their career paths more based on how much they like the job, rather than on how useful the job is to others, which
monetary considerations in a free-market order lead them to do. In rare cases
these things might line up, as in the cases of some doctors and some university
professors (the cases which Singer cherry picks), but in most cases they would
not. Let’s just say that if salaries were equal, there would be a heck of a lot
more ‘freelance writers’, ‘artists’, ‘photographers’, ‘journalists’, and yes,
‘university professors’.
Secondly, differential salaries allow business owners to
entice the labor supply that they need by offering higher pay. Their ability to
offer this higher pay most likely signifies that the person would be more
useful to the consumers being employed by this employer, rather than by his former
employer. Mandating equal salaries for all would obliterate this highly useful
labor allocation mechanism.
Thirdly, people aren’t paid a specific salary just to do ‘a
job’, they are paid a specific salary to do a job at a specific level of
quality. If skill in a position doesn’t lead to a higher salary as it does in a
free-market system, than why bother becoming particularly skillful? Lousy
gardeners would be paid the same as great gardeners. Chefs that make disgusting
food would be paid the same as chefs that make great food. University
professors that deliver terrible lectures and that publish useless research
would be paid the same as professors that deliver great lectures and that
publish highly relevant and groundbreaking research. I could go on at length
but it would start getting tedious.
Fourthly, how about non-salaried people such as business
owners and investors, would they all be allocated the same salary as everyone
else for their activities as well? If yes, the forces that make the market economy’s
businessmen and capitalists responsive to the desires of the consumers would
cease to operate, and the market economy would be destroyed. If no, and these
classes of people were allowed to make all that they could on the market, then
too many intelligent salaried people would rush to become entrepreneurs and day
traders because of the greater monetary rewards that would exist in these
fields.
Finally, this egalitarian scheme would almost certainly
result in less savings-investment and more consumption spending, as poorer
people in most industrial economies, empirically, tend to devote a higher
portion of their income to consumption than richer people do. The result would
be less capital accumulation and probably even capital consumption, which would
reduce the living standards of everyone.
You would think that Singer, who professes to be a
utilitarian, would be more careful before making proposals that have fairly
obvious and significant negative consequences for everyone in society, in the
name of some egalitarian ideal not really grounded in utilitarianism.
Chapter 3: Equality For
Animals?
Singer: “The argument for extending the
principle of equality beyond our own species is simple, so simple that it
amounts to no more than a clear understanding of the nature of the principle of
equal consideration of interests. We have seen that this principle implies that
our concern for others ought not to depend on what they are like, or what
abilities they possess (although precisely what this concern requires us to do
may vary according to the characteristics of those affected by what we do). It
is on this basis that we are able to say that the fact that some people are not
members of our race does not entitle us to exploit them, and similarly the fact
that some people are less intelligent than others does not mean that their
interests may be disregarded. But the principle also implies that the fact that
beings are not members of our species does not entitle us to exploit them, and
similarly the fact that other animals are less intelligent than we are does not
mean that their interests may be disregarded.” 56
Brian: I have tolerated working with the
‘principle of equal consideration of interests’ until this point because it is
basically the universalist utilitarian principle, which can be useful to the
egoist decision-maker in certain circumstances (as I discussed in my critique
of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism). Now
that it is being absurdly applied to animals though, I must object. The only
reasons to work with the principle of equal consideration of interests are: 1.
Because of any sympathy that you might have for members of the human race in
general. 2. In order to convince others to support laws and policies which you
approve of. 3. In order to identify and help preserve rules of conduct that
must be followed if a peaceful and prosperous human society is to be
maintained.
Let us see how these three apply to animals: 1. Some have a
lot of sympathy for ‘cute’ animals such as dogs and dolphins, most have little
to no sympathy for ‘ugly’ animals such as mosquitoes, slugs, and bacteria. Some
(such as I) have sympathy only for animals with whom they have a personal
connection, such as pets. I suspect that the majority of humans have more
sympathy for the average human than they do for the average animal. 2. Animals
cannot be convinced to support your favoured laws and policies, and will not
‘revolt’ if laws and policies which don’t serve their interests are foisted on
them. Thus, this reason doesn’t apply when talking about animals. 3. Treating
animals well is not necessary to maintain a peaceful and prosperous human
society. In fact, the general practice of ‘exploiting’ animals for the benefit
of humans leads to more prosperity for humans than would exist otherwise.
Thus, unless you have a large amount of sympathy for animals
in general (which is rare), it is better to just treat them as economic
commodities, or occasionally as friendly pets. For the animal lovers out there,
they may feel free to be nice to all the animals that they come across, but if
they start trying to use force to make others do the same, they should be ready
to meet violent opposition in response.
Chapter 6: Taking Life:
The Embryo And The Fetus
Singer: “Birth is the most visible possible
dividing line (between non-human life and human life), and the one that would
suit liberals best. It coincides to some extent with our sympathies – we are
less disturbed at the destruction of a fetus we have never seen than at the
death of a being we can all see, hear and cuddle. But is this enough to make
birth the line that decides whether a being may or may not be killed?” 138-139
Brian: In fact, in this case, it is enough.
As was the case with animals, the less sympathy those with power have with a
being, and the less the being in question can defend its interests itself or
have sympathetic champions defend its interests (like children have), the less
worth will be placed on its interests in the calculations of decision-making
actors. The fetus obviously does still have some sympathetic champions, but far
less than the already born human. In addition, protecting the interests of
fetuses is not necessary to maintain a peaceful and prosperous society. In
fact, allowing abortion allows people to pre-empt the harmful economic drain of
unwanted children. It also allows people to better plan their reproductive
lives, which will most likely result in a more economically suitable societal
population level than if abortion were not allowed and unwanted children simply
had to be endured, whether the parents were ready for them or not.
Chapter 8: Rich And
Poor
Singer: “So why are people hungry? Poor
people cannot afford to buy grain grown by farmers in the richer nations. Poor
farmers cannot afford to buy improved seeds, or fertilisers, or the machinery
needed for drilling wells and pumping water. Only by transferring some of the
wealth of the rich nations to the poor can the situation be changed.” 221
Brian: Really? And how many countries have
gone from poor to rich because of free wealth transfers from richer countries?
That’s right, none! Japan, South Korea, Taiwan, Singapore, Hong Kong, none of
these countries went from poor to rich because of egalitarian wealth
redistributions from the richer countries. Residents of the richer countries
did help them to become wealthier faster than they would have without them
though. This was not through wealth redistribution, but through investment of
capital.
In order for the standards of living of residents of a country
to improve, capital must be invested in that country so that its residents can
produce with more and better production tools. Singer mentions this when he
says that poor farmers don’t have access to much-needed machinery and other
production-enhancing tools. Either this capital must be accumulated
domestically through domestic savings, as Britain was forced to do in order to
enable its Industrial Revolution period, or access to this capital can be had
through foreign investment in the country. For the impoverished countries of
today, living in a world containing quite affluent countries, foreign
investment is the quickest and most straightforward way of getting access to
this capital.
Foreign investors will usually be happy to invest in poorer
countries, due to their relatively abundant labor supplies and hence lower wage
levels. But there are certain things that the government of the poorer country
must ensure before this investment will happen: 1. That burdensome restrictions
are not put on the investments. 2. That the investments are not sabotaged
through government taxation or excessive regulation. 3. That the country is a
place where property rights are generally protected. If one examines the
governments of the most impoverished countries, one will find that these conditions
are rarely met to a sufficient degree to encourage foreign investment.
The great thing about foreign investment, as opposed to free
wealth redistribution, is that the investors are led by their own financial
self-interests to engage in these activities that are so beneficial to poorer
countries. In the case of free wealth redistribution, supposedly obligatory
based on woolly ‘moral duties’, most residents of the affluent countries will
try to get out of this burdensome ‘duty’ whenever possible. This is because
wealth redistribution is a winner-loser policy, while foreign investment is a
winner-winner policy, the latter always being more sustainable and beneficial
in the long-run than the former.
Singer: “if it is in our power to prevent
something very bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of
comparable moral significance, we ought to do it. This principle seems uncontroversial.”
229
Brian: Then allow me to controvert it. The
principle assumes a scale of objective ‘goodness/badness’, and a scale of
objective ‘significance/insignificance’. In fact, no such scale exists. Good or
bad, significant or insignificant, will depend on the goals and subjective
valuations of the individual actor.
For instance, if Singer were to tell me, as he probably
would, that rather than buy a new computer with $2000, I ought to use that
$2000 to prolong the lives of starving people in Africa instead, thus
preventing a ‘bad’ that is greater in ‘moral significance’ then the ‘good’ of
buying the computer, I would disagree with him. I would be more than happy to help out the
residents of impoverished countries by recommending what economic policies they
should support for their countries. If they listened, both they and I, now
living in a more generally prosperous world, would be benefitted. But to ask me
to give up something personally valuable
in exchange for a very partial, short-term alleviation of a problem that needs
long-run, fundamental policy and attitude changes to solve, is to ask too much
of my sympathy. The fact is that I care substantially more about my own
interests than I do about the interests of unknown people in countries that I
have never even visited. If this makes me a ‘bad’ person, than I suspect that
the vast majority of the world’s population must also be classified as ‘bad’.
Singer: “No doubt we do instinctively prefer
to help those who are close to us. Few could stand by and watch a child drown;
many can ignore a famine in Africa. But the question is not what we usually do,
but what we ought to do, and it is difficult to see any sound moral
justification for the view that distance, or community membership, makes a
crucial difference to our obligations.” 232
Brian: Perhaps there is no ‘sound moral
justification’ for this standard procedure, but there certainly is an egoistic
justification. Most people care more about those closer to them, whether
geographically or in terms of personal relations. This translates into a
stronger sympathetic bond with the closer people, which in turn translates into
a willingness to take their interests more into consideration when deciding
upon courses of action. There is no need to justify this phenomenon; it’s just
how it is. Any moralistic call to disregard this natural phenomenon is a call
for self-sacrifice, a call to sacrifice what you value more (helping yourself
or those closer to you) for the sake of something that you value less (helping
those further away from you). If all moralistic schemes call for this
self-sacrifice, it is a good reason to reject all notions of morality and embrace
egoism instead.
Chapter 10: The
Environment
Singer: “Now consider again for a moment the
issue of damming the river described at the beginning of this chapter. If the
decision were to be made on the basis of human interests alone, we would
balance the economic benefits of the dam for the citizens of the state against
the loss for bushwalkers, scientists, and others, now and in the future, who
value the preservation of the river in its natural state. We have already seen
that because this calculation includes an indefinite number of future
generations, the loss of the wild river is a much greater cost than we might at
first imagine. Even so, once we broaden the basis of our decision beyond the
interests of human beings, we have much more to set against the economic
benefits of building the dam. Into the calculations must now go the interests
of all the non-human animals who live in the area that will be flooded.”
274-275
Brian: Let’s start with the decision from
the perspective of present generations. Here, on a free-market, the decision is
made based on monetary considerations, which in turn takes into account the
interests of all the expected consumers of the resource in question. Will the
expected monetary revenue, as present income and as future income embodied in
the capital value of the land, be higher if the rights to the river are
acquired and then a dam is built, or if the rights to the river are acquired
and it is preserved as a nature sanctuary? Owners or purchasers of the resource
have a personal, financial interest in making the correct decision from the
perspective of the present values and desires and expected future values and
desires of the consumers.
How about future generations, how can we take into account
their interests? The only non-arbitrary way is through the mechanism of the
capital value of the resource in question: determined by the future expected
income flow of the resource, discounted by the societal rate of
time-preference/general interest rate. Land is a very durable resource, hence
the expected desires of future generations of consumers will be factored into
its capital value/market price, although discounted by the societal rate of
time-preference. Some, like Singer, may not be satisfied with this procedure for
taking the interests of future generations into account, but it is really the
only non-arbitrary one available.
If, for whatever reason, one rejects the free-market method
of resource allocation, the only real alternative is governmental resource
allocation. Thus, government is to be tasked with weighing the interests of
future generations against those of present generations. Firstly, it is unclear
why governments would take this ‘responsibility’ seriously. After all, future
generations don’t vote, and democratic politicians are notorious for their short-term
outlooks. Secondly, even if the government did take this responsibility
seriously, how on earth would they know what the interests of future
generations will be? Can government officials accurately predict the future and
the inner subjective states of mind of unborn people? In reality, what will
happen is that the valuations of the present consumers will be replaced by the
valuations of the relevant government officials when it comes to resource
allocation. If pushed far enough, this would constitute socialism. If not, it
would mean a number of, largely arbitrary, bureaucratic restrictions on private
business.
In addition, for some reason, Singer assumes that if the
hydro-electric plant were built, it would be a more present-oriented decision,
while if the river were preserved, it would be a more future-oriented decision.
This is unjustifiable though. Preserved natural resources are by no means the
only, or even the main, material heritage passed down from generation to
generation. Our present standard of living is due largely to the capital
accumulation accomplished by earlier generations, capital accumulation which
included large investment projects such as hydro-electric dams. If those
investments had not been made in the past, our present standard of living would
not be the same. Economic progress builds off of the economic progress made by
previous generations, it does not take place in a vacuum. For all we know, the
hydro-electric investment could be more future-oriented than preserving the
river, and an automatic assumption to the contrary is not justified.
And then, of course, we have the animals. I think that I have
addressed this issue already in my critique of Singer’s position on animal
rights. Suffice it to say that, for me at least, disrupting animal habitats would
be a pretty minor cost of the proposed policy.
Singer: “We must re-assess our notion of
extravagance. In a world under pressure, this concept is not confined to
chauffeured limousines and Dom Perignon champagne. Timber that has come from a
rainforest is extravagant, because the long-term value of the rainforest is far
greater than the uses to which the timber is put. Disposable paper products are
extravagant, because ancient hardwood forests are being converted into
wood-chips and sold to paper manufacturers. ‘Going for a drive in the country’
is an extravagant use of fossil fuels that contributes to the greenhouse
effect.” 286-287
Brian: Arbitrary value judgments based on
environmentalist dogma are not ‘ethical pronouncements’, they are just opinions
based on some pretty questionable science. Why must rainforests and ancient forests
be preserved at all costs? It is unlikely that humanity will ever run out of
its major natural resources, trees least of all. Trees can actually be planted
and grown, and are best considered as a long-term agricultural crop, not as some
precious, irreplaceable natural resource. Why is preserving these trees necessarily
more important than timber used to build people’s homes or paper used to do
business or to make life easier? Singer may have his own, subjective opinion on
the subject, but others will also have theirs, which may well differ. No
subjective opinion like this can be ‘better’ or ‘more ethical’ than another.
As for using fossil fuels ‘extravagantly’, what is so
extravagant about pleasurable activities? Should humans be forced to live a
dreary life where they only get ‘necessities’? Moreover, the ‘fossil fuels
cause disastrous global warming’ hypothesis is based on some pretty shaky and
uncertain science. At best, this eventuality should only be a probabilistic,
very long-run consideration for humans deciding whether to use fossil fuels or
not, not considered as if it were a scientific certainty of known magnitude.
Chapter 12: Why Act
Morally?
Singer: “When I stand back from my
day-to-day ethical decisions and ask why I should act ethically, I should seek
reasons in the broadest sense, and not allow Kantian preconceptions to deter me
from considering self-interested reasons for living an ethical life. If my
search is successful it will provide me with reasons for taking up the ethical
point of view as a settled policy, a way of living. I would not then ask, in my
day-to-day ethical decision making, whether each particular right action is in
my interests. Instead I do it because I see myself as an ethical person. In
everyday situations, I will simply assume that doing what is right is in my
interests, and once I have decided what is right, I will go ahead and do it,
without thinking about further reasons for doing what is right. To deliberate
over the ultimate reasons for doing what is right in each case would impossibly
complicate my life; it would also be inadvisable because in particular
situations I might be too greatly influenced by strong but temporary desires
and inclinations and so make decisions I would later regret.” 326
Brian: This seems to come very close to my
own view, which is that egoism is the ultimate foundation of decision-making but
that thinking from a universalist utilitarian perspective can often be useful.
Our difference is that Singer thinks it advisable to take up ‘ethical
decision-making’ as a very ‘settled policy’ indeed, whereas I think that it
would be better, for their own interests, if actors were more flexible. Many of
my critiques of Singer up to this point have been based on this difference.
Singer seems to think that if an actor considers so-called ‘ethical
thinking’ to be useful in some regards, it would be advisable for him to settle
on an ‘ethical way of living’ altogether, and to be bound by ethical tenets
forever more. I say that this would be to fall victim to a fixed ideal, and
that more harm than benefit to the actor will result from this decision to be
ethically inflexible. Singer’s own discussion of his preferred ethical system
illustrates why: if a person has convinced himself to ‘think ethically’ and
agrees with Singer, he will have resolved to substantially sacrifice his
interests to lower-paid workers, animals, unrelated people in poorer countries,
ghostly future generations, non-valued ‘environmental goods’, and others. In
the face of such ‘ethical demands’, I think that being flexible about ethical
pronouncements is without a doubt the more sensible policy for individuals.
In the second edition at least, there's a section several pages long at the end of Chapter 3 with the heading "Ethics and Reciprocity" that directly addresses the points you make in your critique of Chapters 1 and 3. There is a lot of good material there, but I think it can be summed up by "No matter how self-interested the origins of ethics may be ... we are capable of reasoning, and reason is not subordinate to self-interest." as well as examples of other groups that would be excluded from moral consideration such as future unborn generations of people and African slaves from the perspective of the slaveowners.
ReplyDelete"... the white slave-traders had no self-interested reason for treating slaves better then they did. The Africans had no way of retaliating. If they had only been contractualists, the slave traders could have rebutted the abolitionists by explaining to them that ethics stops at the boundaries of the community, and since Africans are not part of their community they have no duties to them"