Saturday 1 March 2014

Critique of Ayn Rand's 'The Virtue of Selfishness'

The Virtue of Selfishness[1]

1. The Objectivist Ethics

Rand: “An ultimate value is that final goal or end to which all lesser goals are the means – and it sets the standard by which all lesser goals are evaluated. An organism’s life is its standard of value: that which furthers its life is the good, that which threatens it is the evil.” 11

Brian: How about suicidal people? How about people who want to live only on certain conditions, and would prefer to die if those conditions aren’t met? How about people who derive a lot of enjoyment from actions which risk their lives and health? Life and health are important, for the vast majority of people the most important, standards of value, but they are not the only standards of value. When a choice must be made between greater safety of life and health and another good that the actor finds valuable, only their personal, subjective valuations can decide the issue.


Rand: “In answer to those philosophers who claim that no relation can be established between ultimate ends or values and the facts of reality, let me stress that the fact that living entities exist and function necessitates the existence of values and of an ultimate value which for any given living entity is its own life. Thus the validation of value judgments is to be achieved by reference to the facts of reality. The fact that a living entity is, determines what it ought to do. So much for the issue of the relation between “is” and “ought.” 12

Brian: Just because a living entity is, doesn’t mean that all of its actions must be exclusively directed towards remaining in an ‘is’ state for as long as possible. For instance, let’s say that there is a 40 year old man who smokes, and it is known with reasonable certainty that if he continues smoking, he will die of lung cancer in 30 years at age 70. If he quits smoking, then he has a good chance of extending his lifespan past the age of 70. If we were to say: “You ought to quit smoking”, then this is merely our arbitrary value judgement, there is nothing objective about it. To be objective, we would have to say: “If you want to live past the age of 70, and you believe that you will value this increased lifespan more than the enjoyment that you would derive from smoking for the next 30 years, then you ought to quit smoking”. We present the man with the facts about the causal relations in this particular case, but ultimately it is he who must consult his own subjective, arbitrary value judgements in order to make a decision. There is no objectively ‘correct’ or ‘moral’ answer to this question.


Rand: “The men who attempt to survive, not by means of reason, but by means of force, are attempting to survive by the method of animals. But just as animals would not be able to survive by attempting the method of plants, by rejecting locomotion and waiting for the soil to feed them – so men cannot survive by attempting the method of animals, by rejecting reason and counting on productive men to serve as their prey. Such looters may achieve their goals for the range of a moment, at the price of destruction: the destruction of their victims and their own. As evidence, I offer you any criminal or any dictatorship.” 16

Brian: The analogy is highly imperfect. Individual animals literally cannot survive through the method of plants; any who tried it would die within a few days. Individual humans can and do survive, and sometimes survive on a luxurious level, through loot and plunder of productive humans. I reject the supposed evidence that all looters destroy themselves. Many criminals, particularly the ones involved in organized crime, have done fine for themselves. The same could be said of many dictators: Hu Jintao, Vladimir Putin, Kim Jong Ill, and innumerable kings and nobles throughout history, all seem to have done fine for themselves. And besides, criminals and dictators aren’t the only ones who participate in looting. How about democratic politicians? How about privileged citizens who support and end up benefitting from the coercive actions of their governments?

Now, it is true that if looting and plundering became a general mode of life, everyone, including the looters, would all be worse off, because then no one would be able or willing to produce at all effectively. But that is why most looters try to establish monopolies of looting: to prevent looting from becoming general and from destroying the goose that lays the golden eggs (the looted producers).


Rand: “The basic social principle of the Objectivist ethics is that just as life is an end in itself, so every living human being is an end in himself, not the means to the ends or the welfare of others – and, therefore, that man must live for his own sake, neither sacrificing himself to others nor sacrificing others to himself. To live for his own sake means that the achievement of his own happiness is man’s highest moral purpose.” 19

Brian: This paragraph seems to be expounding egoism, but if so there is a phrase which definitely does not belong and which is not consistent with the rest of the paragraph. This is the phrase: “nor sacrificing others to himself”. If the “achievement of his own happiness is man’s highest moral purpose”, then why shouldn’t he seek to sacrifice others to himself if, by doing so, he can increase his own happiness? In order to minimize such attempts, men would do well to ensure that their social institutions are set up in such a way that people can rarely benefit themselves through the sacrifice of others. But moralistic pronouncements alone, not backed by real sanctions, mean nothing to the egoist intent on advancing his own happiness.


Rand: “I quote from Galt’s speech (from Atlas Shrugged): “Happiness is a state of non-contradictory joy – a joy without penalty or guilt, a joy that does not clash with any of your values and does not work for your own destruction.”” 20

Brian: I cannot accept this definition of happiness. Throughout life, men make an innumerable series of choices between a and b. If a is preferred over b, and one devotes one’s finite resources to obtaining a rather than b, than b can be considered the cost (opportunity cost) of obtaining a. In most cases, the actor does not consider a to be positive and b to be negative. Rather, the actor considers b to be positive, but a to be more positive, and hence he chooses a. But this means that b is still a valued good, even if a is a more valued good. The “penalty” of choosing to obtain a is not obtaining b, the “joy” of obtaining a clashes with another one of your values, namely, the value which indicates the desirability of b.

For instance, a man is faced with a choice: buy a sugary chocolate bar which he loves the taste of, or buy a healthy and nutritious fruit and nut bar which he doesn’t particularly like the taste of. Let us assume that the two bars cost the same amount of money and are available at the same location. Pursuing the pleasure of tasty things versus ensuring bodily health, these are the two values at stake, values which most people hold to a greater or lesser extent. Rand implies that one cannot obtain ‘true happiness’ from either choice. The two values are in many cases contradictory, one must often choose between them. What is the poor seeker of “a state of non-contradictory joy” to do? Either way, he cannot obtain his goal. And this is the case for a great deal of the day-to-day choices facing human beings. Thus, I think that we must reject Rand’s exacting definition of happiness, and stick with the subjective/personal definition of it.  


Rand: “To take “whatever makes one happy” as a guide to actions means: to be guided by nothing but one’s emotional whims. Emotions are not tools of cognition; to be guided by whims – by desires whose source, nature and meaning one does not know – is to turn oneself into a blind robot, operated by unknowable demons ( by one’s stale evasions), a robot knocking its stagnant brains out against the walls of reality which it refuses to see.” 20

Brian: Oh no, apparently I am a blind robot with stagnant brains! The reality which Rand refuses to see here is that one cannot just determine what will make one happy and what won’t according to some external standard. Imagine that a devoted Randian is determined to make his happiness ‘rational’. He decides that he will henceforth only attain happiness from things which objectively advance his life. Anything that is good for his material prosperity (material means of sustaining life) or for his bodily health (bodily means of sustaining life), he determines, will henceforth make him happy. Anything that conflicts with these goals, he determines, will henceforth make him miserable.

Before, he was somewhat of an artistic and literary type, arts and literature made him happy and he wanted to do something in those fields for a living. Now, he realizes how misguided he was: he could make far more money as a chemical engineer! Thus, he determines that henceforth, anything that makes him a better and more qualified chemical engineer will make him happy. He enrolls in the chemical engineering program at his university. He slogs through the courses, determined that they will make him happy. And yet: they really don’t. He finds calculus, scientific experimentation, and engineering design tasks to be dreary and dull. He tries to convince himself that since these things will lead to a more prosperous future for him, they really should make him happy. But, no matter how hard he tries, he simply does not derive any enjoyment from these things, and secretly longs to return to his novels, poems, plays, and history books.

While this was going on, our devoted Randian also decided that he would eat healthy foods and exercise regularly to maintain his bodily health in top condition. Before, he derived great enjoyment from eating sweet and greasy foods, and didn’t particularly care for physical activity, doing some every now and then only begrudgingly. No matter, he resolved that he would henceforth derive as much happiness from eating healthy foods and from exercising regularly than he had before from eating unhealthy foods and from his more passive leisure activities. And yet: despite his resolution, these things really didn’t make him happy. While trying to derive enjoyment from eating plain chicken breast with broccoli and quinoa, he secretly longed for a Big Crunch Sandwich from KFC. While trying to derive enjoyment from vigorous exercise, he secretly longed to sit in front of his television and marathon-watch the new season of Game of Thrones.  

Why did our Randian fail? Why couldn’t he transform useful things into enjoyable things? It would make everything so much easier for him if he could have! But alas, like it or not, happiness is ultimately based on “emotional whim”. This doesn’t mean that man’s conduct must be guided by every spur-of-the-moment whim that happens to come to his mind. Man has the ability to choose useful things, things that are expected to produce happiness in the long-run, over enjoyable things, things that are expected to produce relatively immediate happiness in the short-run. More future-oriented people will tend to choose useful things over enjoyable things more often that more present-oriented people. But not even future-oriented people have the power of transforming, on command, something that involves a sacrifice of some short-term happiness in exchange for a greater amount of long-run happiness, into something that is both enjoyable in the short-term and good for the long-term. If you can prove to me that there are people that can do this, I would really love to know how they do it, for such an ability would make life incalculably easier. Alas though, I am dubious that such an ability exists at all.


10. Collectivized Ethics

Rand: “If a man speculates on what “society” should do for the poor, he accepts thereby the collectivist premise that men’s lives belong to society and that he,  as a member of society, has the right to dispose of them, to set their goals or to plan the “distribution” of their efforts.” 57

Brian: That is only one possibility. The other possibility is that the man is an egoist who would derive personal enjoyment from the poor of his community being helped, but who is unwilling to fully pay the cost of this himself. He resorts to advocating for ‘societal’ coercion for the sake of his own well-being. He doesn’t think that he has a ‘right’ to dispose of the property of people within his community, nor does he think that they have a ‘right’ to retain their property for themselves. The egoist doesn’t deal in ‘rights’, but in expediency. Is it likely that, through advocating for a certain form of government coercion intended to help poor people, the egoist’s goal of seeing the poor people in his community helped could be advanced, at less cost to himself than if he had undertaken the task by himself and without advocating for coercion? If so, he will advocate for the coercion, if not, he will not. Determining whether this is the case will involve a complex calculation of costs and benefits of the advocacy, some of them short-term, some of them long-term. Detailed knowledge of economics, politics, and sociology would help make this decision an informed one. But these kinds of complex calculations are the ultimate foundation of egoistic political decision-making, not the (sometimes useful) short-cut of saying that people either do or don’t have a ‘right’ to do something or other.

            


   



[1] Ayn Rand, The Virtue of Selfishness (New York: Penguin Group, 1964).

No comments:

Post a Comment