‘Leftist’
Statism, the ideology that politicians and ideologues considered to be ‘on the
left’ of the political spectrum use to justify government intervention,
consists of three main pillars: belief in extensive government control over
business, egalitarianism, and Social Safety Net-ism. We will examine and
critique these pillars in this post to see what ‘left-wing’ statism is all
about and why I think it is best to avoid most of it.
1. Government control over business:
Leftist
statists generally believe that government should be relatively heavily
involved in the business world, whether through ownership of government
enterprises, nationalization of industries, or regulation of otherwise private
businesses. Some justify this on Marxist grounds, arguing that private business
exploits their workers and/or rip-offs their customers regularly. Some justify
it by pointing to positive and negative externalities, and in recent years,
environmentalism has been used to justify government ownership and regulation.
The Marxist justification rests on
the notion of ‘economic power’ being just as bad if not worse than power to
inflict physical damage, which I am critical of here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/04/why-physical-violence-is-useful-basic.html
The general externalities
justification can be valid in some cases, but must be used with care and is
liable to be abused, which I discuss here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/economic-externalities-raison-detre-for.html
The environmentalist justification is
generally overplayed by leftists, and there are many better ways besides heavy
handed government intervention to deal with any environmental problems that
might arise, which I discuss in the series of posts starting here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/thoughts-on-environmentalism-general.html
However it is justified, whether
there is some truth to the justifications or not, there are certain significant
disadvantages of government interventions with business and government
ownership of businesses which cannot be dismissed lightly by anyone seeking to
make an informed decision on whether to support economic freedom or government
interventionism in a particular case. These apply to any government-provided
service that can be provided by private enterprise, and to a lesser extent to
government regulation of private business, which is when the government
arrogates to itself a portion of the ownership/management functions of an
otherwise privately-owned business. They are:
1. Lack of market pricing for the government service and less
importance placed on profit-and-loss calculations impairs the processes of capitalistic
economic calculation that serve as a guide to private business. Political considerations
(what will be popular or allow the incumbent government to maintain power) will
correspondingly play a greater role in decision-making (for more on the
benefits of economic calculation, see tip 5 here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/02/5.html).
2. The funds necessary to start and usually to continue
operating the government enterprise are collected through taxation levies on
the population. This will tend to lead to a more cavalier use of the initial
‘investment’ funds than private business would, who only receive investment
funds by convincing investors that it is a promising investment, well-worth
taking a risk on. In addition, when gathering private investment funds, the
funds available are limited by the willingness of investors to put their money
in one particular venture rather than in any other. When levying taxation money
to fund a government service though, it is impossible to know exactly how much
to levy to fund that particular service over other government services, or over
leaving the money to private individuals. The willingness of investors and
their consideration of the prospects for profit of a particular venture over
any other sets a limit to the amount of private investment going into any
enterprise, but this limit does not exist for government services. Also, the
taxation levy will generally fall more heavily on the funds of richer people,
which will tend to undermine incentives to produce for the consumers and will most
likely undermine capital accumulation (discussed in more detail here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/issue-analysis-higher-taxes-on-wealthy.html)
3. Either through legislation or through the unfair advantage
of being able to get funding through coercive taxation levies, government
enterprises are able to legislate away (by prohibiting competition) or drive
away all of their private competitors. As a result, not faced with fierce
competition as private enterprises are, government enterprises are able to be
more lacklustre and less cost effective in their service to the consumers.
4. When it comes to pricing, government enterprises tend to
either charge subsidized prices, below what would have been the market price
for the service, or monopoly prices, above what would have been the competitive
market price for the service due to their legal or quasi-legal monopoly
position in the industry. If they charge below-market, subsidized prices, the
service is not allocated efficiently to the consumers who want it most
urgently, and shortages result because of the government artificially
stimulating demand without an increase in supply. ‘Free’ roads are a good
example of this, and constant traffic jams their logical result. If the
government charges monopoly prices in order to try not to run too big a deficit
to be paid for by taxpayer money, then access to the service is artificially reduced
below what it otherwise would have been if free-market competition had been
allowed to operate to reduce costs and prices, and improve quality, in the
industry, as it so often does.
The main
error in this aspect of leftist, statist ideology is to either ignore, deny, or
unjustifiably downplay these important disadvantages of government ownership of
business.
(Note: For a great, succinct critique of government-provided
services, check out the following excerpt from Murray Rothbard’s Power and Market, found here: http://mises.org/daily/1471)
2. Egalitarianism:
There is no
getting around the fact that something about an inequality of material wealth
and income among members of a society just bothers leftist statists, and thus
egalitarianism becomes a major pillar of their ideology. One can sometimes
convince holders of this ideology that a certain degree of inequality of
material wealth and income is necessary in a prosperous society to maintain
incentives to produce for the consumers and such, but they will tend not to be
happy about it and will constantly seek ways to reduce it.
There is certainly something to be said for
considering more material equality among members of a society, other things
equal, as a good thing. Though we cannot say so with scientific certainty, it
is likely that a billionaire accumulating another billion dollars would result
in less of an increase in general happiness than 10000 people with modest
incomes being able to accumulate an extra hundred-thousand dollars each. The
problem is that, unless this change in income distribution occurs through the
play of market forces, other things are necessarily not equal. If it is brought
about through government tax and transfer policies, then incentives to produce
for the consumers and capital accumulation are reduced, while harmful
government bloat is encouraged, all resulting in a tendency towards a decline
in the material standards of living of all members in a society. For a full
discussion of this, see: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/issue-analysis-higher-taxes-on-wealthy.html
However,
even if an egalitarian were to recognize these negative effects of egalitarian
government policies (which most do not), the question remains: how highly does
the social thinker evaluate egalitarianism, taken on its own? More
specifically: how much societal material wealth is the social thinker willing
to sacrifice in pursuit of egalitarianism?
To these
questions, I, personally, would respond: egalitarianism is generally overrated
as a good. if we are to value ‘fairness’ in the distribution of material goods
as a good in its own right, what’s wrong with market-meritocracy (reward
through ability to serve the consumers) as a standard? Most egalitarians
probably wouldn’t be convinced to change their views because of this answer,
and I wouldn’t really expect them to. Whether a more egalitarian distribution
of material goods or a more market-meritocratic distribution of material goods
(divorced for now from the respective consequences of their implementation) is
more ‘fair’ is, I think, a bit of a subjective question. For whatever reason, I
think the latter is fairer, while for whatever reason, others think the former
is fairer. I don’t think that there’s a rational way, divorced from the
utilitarian effects of the implementation of these ideals, of evaluating which
standard of distribution is fairer, just as there’s no rational way, divorced
from say, their respective health effects, of evaluating whether chocolate or
vanilla ice cream is ‘better’. The answers will change depending on whose
subjective preferences are being consulted.
How then, to critique the egalitarian
aspect of leftist statist ideology? Even if we can’t ultimately critique
people’s subjective evaluations of egalitarianism as an isolated good, we can
critique egalitarianism based on the other utilitarian effects of its
implementation through the coercive power of government, which we have done
above. We can also critique the conviction, found among many, though perhaps
not all, egalitarians, which holds that egalitarianism, is objectively, morally
better than any other standard for evaluating the distribution of material goods
among members of a society. These people are certainly entitled to their
opinion, but at the end of the day it must be recognized that this is merely a
value judgement that not everyone accepts. As such, it should not be employed
as some kind of intellectual trump-card, used to banish any objections to
egalitarian policies by merely proclaiming them to be ‘immoral’.
3. Social Safety Net-ism:
Social
Safety Net-ism is the doctrine that government has a right and a duty to ensure,
using funds levied from taxpayers, that people living in the territory under
their rule do not die or suffer serious physical damage due solely to their
material poverty. This is the aspect of leftist statist ideology that I, and I
think many others, sympathize the most with. Leftists seem to realize this, and
as such use Social Safety Net-ism as the vanguard of much of their
argumentation in favour of government intervention. Consider the following
disparaging remark about libertarianism from leftist political comedian Bill
Maher, saying that while Social Security and Medicare are flawed programs: “it
beats stepping over lepers and watching human skeletons shit in the river and I
also like not seeing those things. I’m selfish that way!”. Here, Maher is using
Social Safety Net-ism to try to discredit an entire intellectual movement and
to defend some pretty questionable and controversial government policies. Of
course, libertarians contend that such horrors would never occur in a
prosperous free-market society due to the greater general material prosperity
that would result from greater economic freedom, combined with private
charitable efforts that would almost certainly grow if they weren’t being
crowded-out by government programs. Even if we were to ignore or reject such
considerations though, Maher’s criticism is still misleading.
We see why
when we ask the question: is the entire apparatus of the United States welfare
state really necessary to prevent people from dying in the streets? Is that
really the sole purpose of these programs and policies? Obviously, the answer
is no. Social Security and Medicare have clear egalitarian motivations, and
both are premised on the assumption that government will be able to make better
use of the money collected from taxpayers through these programs than
individuals would. Medicare is also premised on the assumption that a private
medical market is not the way to go, and that heavy government interventions
are necessary to ‘correct’ the alleged ‘failings’ of that market. In fact, if
the entire current US welfare state was scrapped, and simply replaced by a
welfare system that came to the aid of truly impoverished people who really
were at risk of death or serious physical damage due solely to poverty, the
principle of Social Safety Net-ism would be preserved in a form that would cost
the taxpayers much less of their funds and liberties. What wouldn’t be
preserved would be the first two principles of leftist statism which we
discussed earlier, the desirability of government control of business and
egalitarianism, principles that are embedded in the vast majority of government
welfare programs.
Thus,
leftist statists, particularly when confronting libertarians, often pull an
intellectual bait-and-switch maneuver. They use their most sympathetic
principle, Social Safety Net-ism, to argue against libertarianism in general,
using it to defend policies that also involve a heavy dose of government control
of business and egalitarian principles.
Personally,
I sympathize enough with Social Safety Net-ism to advocate it as a political
principle, but I am always careful to separate it from government ownership of
business and egalitarian principles. For my reasons for advocating Social
Safety Net-ism, and my proposal for a government welfare system that advances
this principle and this principle alone, see the following: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/issue-analysis-welfare-social-safety-net.html.
Besides
unjustifiably lumping it together with policies that clearly advance government
control of business and egalitarian principles, leftist statists also tend to
overrate the importance that Social Safety Net-ism policies would take on in a
free-market society. This is because they tend to underrate the extent of
upward social mobility in a free-market society and mistake it for a caste
society, an idea which I criticize here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/04/why-free-market-society-is-not-caste.html
No comments:
Post a Comment