‘Rightist’
Statism, the ideology that politicians and ideologues considered to be ‘on the
right’ of the political spectrum use to justify government intervention,
consists of three main pillars: legislated ‘morality’, nationalism, and
conservatism. We will examine and critique these pillars in this post to see
what ‘right-wing’ statism is all about and why I think it is best to avoid most
of it.
1. Legislated ‘morality’:
One
important pillar of right-wing statism is legislated ‘morality’, also known as
socially conservative policies. According to this idea, it is the job of the
State to ensure that people adhere to some code of personal morality, usually
based on a religion. The result is a series of what libertarians call
‘victimless crime’ legislation: legislation that makes some personal behaviors
which don’t involve a physical transgression on the person or property of other
citizens illegal, restricted, and punishable. Prohibition of recreational drugs
and restrictions on marriage between gay people are examples of such
legislation.
There are
two main problems with such legislation. The first is that the subjective
utility of the person whose activities are being restricted is certainly being
reduced, for the sake of the questionable benefits of busy bodies feeling that
their neighbours are ‘more moral’ now. Though such a statement cannot be made
with scientific precision as subjective utility cannot be measured or compared
interpersonally, I would venture to guess that the gay person who is prevented
from marrying their partner, or the recreational enjoyer of marijuana from
indulging in their pastime, are more injured than busy bodies being slightly
more satisfied with the ‘good morals’ of their neighbours as a result of the
legislation are benefitted.
The second
main problem is the general principle such legislation embodies, or the
precedents it sets for further government action. Once it is admitted that ‘personal
morality police’ is a legitimate function of government, the ideological way is
cleared for all kinds of tyrannical legislation. Forcing a particular religion
on the populace, prohibiting the consumption of alcoholic beverages for being
‘immoral’, and even prohibiting certain classes of people from wearing certain
styles of clothing through ‘sumptuary laws’ are all extensions of this general
principle that governments have tried in the past. Prohibiting ‘unhealthy’
foods, or violent video games and movies, or pornography, are other ways that
governments could extend this general principle, to say nothing about the possible
further extension of the principle to political and cultural statements,
censoring those that are deemed ‘immoral’.
Ultimately,
personal morality just seems too arbitrary to be profitably imposed by force,
as opposed to the minimalist moral code that protects people’s persons and
properties against physical violence, which is easy to define and the
near-consistent following of which can be demonstrated to be materially
beneficial for almost everyone in society. When a version of personal morality
is to be imposed by force, the question always is: whose version of personal
morality? The answer will be the loudest political interest group that manages
to capture a share of political power, and there is no reason to believe that
their version of personal morality is more worthy of being imposed on others by
force than anyone else’s, to say the least.
2. Nationalism:
Nationalism
can be divided into two sub-categories: ethnic nationalism and civic
nationalism. Ethnic nationalism is an ideology that says that the interests of
‘your ethnic group’ (however that is defined) takes precedence over the
interests of any ‘other ethnic group’, and that one should usually try to
advance the interests of your ethnic group even if by so doing the interests of
other ethnic groups are demonstrably harmed. Civic nationalism is similar, but
rather than ethnic groups, it refers to ‘your country (territorial political
grouping)’ and any ‘other country (territorial political grouping)’. For
example, French ethnic nationalism would be concerned with the French ethnic
group, probably meaning French-speaking, light-skinned people whose families
have inhabited the territory in the political grouping known as France for a
relatively long period of time (although the concept of ethnicity is largely
not grounded in biology and thus is quite malleable). French civic nationalism,
on the other hand, would be concerned with everyone living and accepted as
citizens in the territorial political grouping known as France, regardless of
their ancestry, mother-tongue, or skin colour.
In either
case, those who identify with ‘right-wing’ ideology tend to be proponents of
one of these nationalisms, or sometimes both. An example of an ethnic
nationalist policy would be forcing the language of the majority ethnic group
on the minority ethnic groups living in the country through public schooling,
or the Swiss policy of banning minarets on any mosques that might be built. An
example of a civic nationalist policy would be protectionism through tariff
barriers, supposedly in order to develop certain industries in that country.
These
nationalist ideologies are often used to criticize free-market ideals because,
it is alleged, putting these ideals in place might not immediately benefit the
ethnic group or country of the criticizer. It is possible for there to be some
truth in this statement, for the simple reason that ethnic groups and countries
are not analytical units in economic theory. Free-market economic theory
concerns itself with the individual, a grouping of individuals combined for a
common purpose known as a firm, corporation, or association, and with the world
market society as a whole. It does not say that economic freedom will
especially benefit ethnic group A over ethnic group B, or territorial political
grouping A over territorial political grouping B. It says that economic freedom
will, in the long-run, tend to benefit the material interests of the world
market society and the individuals who constitute it, over any other form of
economic/political arrangement.
The problem
with nationalist ideologies intellectually is that they tend to be
short-sighted and hypocritical. This is because they ignore the long-term
consequences of their nationalist ideologies if they were universalized and
nationalist policies were being carried out all over the world. For instance,
take protectionist policies. Proponents of protectionism imply that members of
their territorial political grouping should not be satisfied with the place
that their territory will be assigned by market forces in a free-market,
international division of labour, world market society. Rather, they want
‘their’ countries to develop certain kinds of industries which they deem
‘superior’, even if to do so they must put up tariff barriers to keep out
‘foreign’ competition in those industries. Nowadays, high-end manufacturing and
scientific industries seem to be the protectionists’ industries of choice. The
problem with this is that the whole point of an international division of
labour, or any division of labour for that manner, is so that different people
and different geographical areas can specialize in different things, and then can exchange
their respective products. If every country has a copy of the industries of
every other, kept artificially profitable through competition-excluding tariff
barriers, than there’s no more international division of labour, and everyone
is poorer as a result due to less specialization and less efficient utilization
of the earth’s land and natural resources.
I am not
going to talk about protectionism too much more here, mainly because I have
discussed it at length in a previous post, found here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/03/the-dark-side-of-historical-prosperity.html
Here,
suffice it to say that nationalist policies must, by their very nature, always
be sectional policies: policies designed to benefit only a section of humanity.
Fighting for these sectional advantages through policies that undermine the
free-market order make the people of the world as a whole poorer, and would
make the people of the world a lot poorer if nationalist policies were
universalized and pursued consistently by every territorial political grouping.
3. Conservatism:
‘Right-wing’
and ‘Conservative’ seem to be almost synonymous in today’s political
vocabulary, and many people identified as ‘right-wing’ adopt the title of
‘conservative’ with pride. What exactly does conservatism mean as an ideology
though?
From my
understanding of it, conservatism seems to suggest that rapid change is to be
avoided and that political ‘traditions’ must have something good in them and
should not be tampered with lightly. Thus, American Conservatives often praise
the ‘founding fathers’ of the United States and the Constitution that they
drafted, and advocate for a return to their political ideals. Canadian
Conservatives often sought to have closer political and cultural ties with the
imperial/former imperial mother country of Great Britain, and nowadays want to
keep the British monarchical traditions going strong in Canada.
The tricky
thing about conservatism is that it does not really represent a set of concrete
political ideals, but rather an aversion to rapid change and a championing of
whatever the political ‘tradition’ of their country happens to be. Thus, the
original Conservatives, the ‘Tories’ of late 17th century and early
18th century Britain, sought a return to the days of hereditary
absolute monarchy, as opposed to the ‘Whigs’ who supported the ‘Glorious
Revolution ‘and constitutional monarchy. Absolute monarchy was not the
political tradition on which the United States was founded, but rather
limited-government, liberal republicanism, so it is this ideology that the
American Conservatives of today are said to favor. However, American
Conservatives also seem to be enamoured with presidents such as Abraham
Lincoln, a protectionist, anti-states’ rights president, and Theodore
Roosevelt, a ‘trust-busting’, imperialistic president, not exactly the governing
styles that the founding fathers had in mind.
Thus, if we were to be ungenerous, we could
just call conservatism an ideology that calls for slavish devotion to an
arbitrary selection of the ‘traditions’ of an arbitrarily chosen historical
period in the past. If we were to be more generous though, we could interpret
conservatism as an ideology which seeks out what policies ‘worked’ in the past
and calls for their implementation in the present. We could also interpret it
as an ideology that recognizes that rapid societal changes are usually bad
news, and that tried and true principles and slow progress are safer than
schemes which seek to rapidly ‘remake’ society.
To be fair
to conservatism, it is this generous interpretation that we will focus our
critique on. As for the first point, finding out what ‘worked’ in the past is
simply another way of saying that empirical historical studies can be useful
for social thinkers. I would agree with this statement: empirical historical
studies, coupled with logical theorizing, can help keep the theory grounded in
reality. Also, as I have noted in my issue analyses, social theories only come
up with qualitative effects, not quantitative ones, and thus empirical
research, though never completely decisive, can help suggest what magnitudes of
the qualitative effects predicted tend to appear. The problem is that
conservative ideologies tend to lead social thinkers to be too fixated on what
happened in the past, to the detriment of their logical theorizing and their
consistent recognition of the difference between correlation and causation.
The American Conservatives’ love for
the founding fathers, Abraham Lincoln, and Theodore Roosevelt mentioned above
is a good example of what being overly fixated on the past can do. Ideologically,
the policies of Lincoln and Teddy Roosevelt were not logical outgrowths of the
ideals of the founding fathers. But, for the Conservative fixated on the past,
the founding fathers’ ideology seem to have ‘worked’ in one historical period,
while Lincoln and Roosevelt’s ideologies seem to have ‘worked’ in another. But
this is not helpful for deciding on which political ideology to adopt in the
present, should it be the founding fathers’ limited government ideology, or
Lincoln, Teddy Roosevelt, and their successors’ bigger government ideology?
Which is, as American Conservatives like to put it, ‘more American’? Ultimately,
only social and economic theories and targeted
historical research to illustrate them and/or to help ascertain what the
magnitude of their predicted effects are likely to be can decide this question,
a procedure which conservative ideology is generally not conducive to.
As for the
second point, it is true that in the past, many political attempts at rapid
societal changes, such as the radical stages of the French Revolution or the
Bolshevik Revolution in Russia, were bad news. But the rapid socio-economic
changes, made possible by a certain political environment, which constituted
the Industrial Revolution, and the pretty radical, for the time, American
Revolution and experiment in republican self-government itself, are examples of
rapid societal changes that probably worked out for the better. It is somewhat
ironic that modern American Conservatives take the ideals of the founding
fathers and their young, radical, experimental new republican country as the
‘traditions’ to be preserved if they are so against rapid societal and
political changes.
In general though, there is definitely
something to be said for the conservative emphasis on ‘tried and true’
principles and slow progress, as opposed to radical social schemes. I am very
aware that the general principles represented by policies are very important,
and that policies that set up a dangerous general principle are dangerous
themselves. However, it is possible that the general political principles
currently being applied are dangerous
and bad principles, and thus should be reversed and replaced by better ones.
For example, take Britain in 1980. Since the late 1940s, Britain had been run
by both Labour and Conservative governments, whose policies were heavily
influenced by social-democratic ideology and political principles. When
Margaret Thatcher, as leader of the Conservative Party, became Prime Minister
in 1980, rhetorically denounced social-democratic political principles, and
made some fairly significant changes in policy direction, this was by no means
a ‘conservative’ move. Some might say it was a ‘radical’ shift away from the
prevalent political principles of the last three decades. Whether the old
social-democratic principles or the new Thatcherite political principles were
ultimately better then becomes the question for social thinkers.
All this is
to say that it is their theoretical and empirical soundness rather than their
oldness or ‘tried and true-ness’ that makes a political principle, such as the
sanctity of private property, worth preserving. A very old political principle,
found in Ancient Egypt in the 3000s BC, that the ruler has the right to use
slave labour to build himself a ridiculously expensive tomb, is not, I think
worth preserving just because it is old, or because subtle variations of it
were adopted by many absolute despots throughout human history.
Thus,
whatever is true in conservatism, can be adopted quite easily into social
thinking by just recognising that material progress takes some time, even given
the right institutional conditions, that empirical historical research can be
useful, and that logically sound general principles should not be compromised
based on political whim. The rest can be profitably discarded.
No comments:
Post a Comment