Saturday, 3 May 2014

The Mighty Contract And Its Prerequisites (Legal)

            In his article, ‘Consideration and Form’, renowned American legal philosopher and contract law scholar Lon Fuller wrote the following about ‘private autonomy’, which he considered central to contract law:

“This principle simply means that the law views private individuals as possessing a power to effect, within certain limits, changes in their legal relations. The man who conveys property to another is exercising this power; so is the man who enters a contract. When a court enforces a promise it is merely arming with legal sanction a rule or lex previously established by the party himself. This power of the individual to effect changes in his legal relations with others is comparable to the power of a legislature. It is, in fact, only a kind of political prejudice which causes us to use the word “law” in one case and not in the other, a prejudice which did not deter the Romans from applying the word lex to the norms established by private agreement.”[1]
           
           In light of this, I define ‘Contract’ as follows: A voluntary, mutually agreed-upon, and mutually beneficial change in two parties’ legal relations with one another. Contracts can take the form of a transfer of legally recognized property titles (conveyance contract), the making of a legally binding promise (promissory contract), or the waiver of some existing legal liability for causing injury or trespass (liability contract).
            
           At first glance, these ideas might seem strange. The common view of law is of rules imposed from on high by legislatures and judges. But, through contract, private individuals can make law for themselves in many fields, and can use the apparatus of judges and police officers as tools for making these laws enforceable.
            
           This system of private, voluntary law making through contract actually has a pretty broad and important scope. The bulk of what we know as property, contract, and tort law is within its realm. There are really only a few things which ‘law imposed from on high’ must deal with before voluntarism can do the rest. These are: 1. Assignment of initial property rights. 2. Determining when a contract exists and interpreting its meaning. 3. Determining when an injury or trespass is ‘caused’ by another person or not. 4. Setting Default Rules. 5. Maintaining the legal apparatus. Let us consider these five in turn.
            
           Property, contract, and tort law all revolve around property rights in persons and things. The voluntary system of exchanges and contracts can modify property rights in all kinds of important and beneficial ways, but it cannot establish an initial assignment of these rights. The first question the law must answer with regard to the initial assignment of property rights is: who owns the labor and the body of each individual person? Anglo-Saxon Common Law (and any other civilized legal system) answers: the individual person themselves! When it comes to children, the answer is a bit more complicated, but for adults, the individual adult is recognized as initially possessing the right to bodily integrity (freedom from gratuitous bodily harm imposed by others) and the right to dispose of their own labor powers as they see fit.
            
           The second question is: how does private ownership in previously unowned land and material goods get established? Anglo-Saxon Common Law generally answers: the first person to possess and use the unowned land or material good should be the legally recognized owner of it. The pioneer who clears a patch of unowned wilderness to start a farm is recognized as owning that patch; the gatherer who picks a basket of berries from an unowned forest is recognized as owning that basket of berries. Robbery of a parcel of land or a material good does not establish the robber’s legal title to that good, unless a significant span of time (usually 50 years) has passed, in which case the heir or the purchaser of the robber’s lands or goods will get full, uncontestable legal title to them. One can certainly think of other ways of establishing legal ownership in previously unowned land and material goods. For instance, the government with military power over a territory could claim all privately unowned land for itself temporarily, and then auction it off to the highest private bidder. Whichever way or combination of ways the legal system chooses, the important thing, for the purposes of establishing a legal system based on free contract, is that there be a recognized way of turning unowned things into legally recognized private property.
            
           Once the question of initial property rights is settled, people can start entering into contracts with one another to modify and transfer these property rights. People can exchange their labor and material possessions for the labor and material possessions of other people, and will do so as long as the deal is mutually beneficial. For simple hand-to-hand exchanges, all the legal system has to do is recognize the changed titles to property. 

           Another thing people can do, and this is vital for any economy above the primitive level, is exchange legally binding promises to do something for, or to give something to, the other person. For example, one person can promise to work at a task for an employer for two weeks, and in exchange, the employer can promise to pay the worker a definite sum of money at the end of the two weeks. Or, a farmer could promise to sell a grain trader a certain quantity of wheat at a certain price on a specified date in the future, in exchange for the grain trader’s promise to buy this certain quantity of wheat at a certain price on a specified date in the future (a futures contract). Or, a creditor could agree to give a debtor a certain sum of money in the present, in exchange for the promise of the debtor to repay this sum of money, with a specified sum of interest added on, by a specified date in the future. In all of these cases, the legally binding aspect comes in when the person who made such a promise seeks to break that promise. If they do so, the apparatus of the law comes in and forces the breaker of the promise to pay out the agreed-upon (or the default) damages to the victim for breaching the contract. This legal sanction helps to make these kinds of promissory transactions, especially ones involving complete strangers, more certain, and therefore more effective.
            
            In order to enforce a contract, the legal system must first determine whether a contract between two parties in fact exists or not, and if it does, what exactly the content of the agreement is. This task cannot be done through private contracts, because the point in question is whether a contract exists in the first place and how it is to be interpreted if it does. Thus, here is the second thing that ‘law imposed from on high’ must deal with in order to facilitate the system of free contract. The legal system must determine when a contract has the mutual assent of the two parties, and must interpret the substance of any mutual agreement that exists. If it failed to do these things effectively, than the legal system might be imposing obligations on the parties that they did not mutually agree to, or it might be failing to enforce obligations that the parties wanted to be legally enforceable. The legal system, which in this context is supposed to be acting as the tool of the contracting parties, could end up becoming an ineffective tool, or could end up transforming from a tool into a tyrant.
            
           If people have a legally recognized property right in their persons and material property, than the legal system will generally seek to protect the individual’s person and material property against invasion, injury, and trespass by another party. Here is where tort law comes in. Just as, in the case of promissory contracts, the legal system had to determine when a contract existed and what its contents were, here the legal system has to determine when an invasion, injury, or trespass exists, which party, if any, caused these events, and what percentage of the causal responsibility for the event lies with that party. This is the third thing that ‘law imposed from on high’ must deal with in order to facilitate the system of free contract.
            
           The fourth task of ‘law imposed from on high’ is to set the ‘Default Rules’. The system of free contract is all about allowing parties to alter their legal relations with one another as they see fit, as long as the alteration is mutually agreed-upon by the relevant parties. But sometimes, contingencies arise which the parties did not plan for or take into account when negotiating their contracts. If the contingency does arise, there must be a ‘default’ behavior adopted by the legal system in relation to this contingency. This behavior could be doing nothing at all, or it could consist of following a default rule that will apply if this contingency arises and the parties say nothing about it in their contract.
            
            Some legal scholars think that default rules should be set based on what most contracting parties in specific circumstances would have wanted anyway. Others, such as Randy Barnett, think that the actual content of the default rules is less important than that they help reduce misunderstandings between the parties about the terms that will apply in the event of a dispute. Even if most parties choose to contract around these rules, by doing so the likelihood that both parties are consenting to the same thing increases[2].  As such, according to Barnett: “contract law should confine itself to common-sense default rules that unsophisticated parties would expect.”[3]  I tend to agree with this latter view, as it is more conducive to the system of free contract I am describing. By setting simple default rules that conform to the likely expectations of unsophisticated parties, we can both help ensure that unsophisticated parties aren’t taken advantage of, and encourage sophisticated parties to raise the issue with unsophisticated parties if they wish to contract around this default rule. The idea is to encourage parties to actually work out mutually agreeable terms for themselves, rather than to try to impose sophisticated default rules from on high that judges and legal scholars think are agreeable and should be adopted by the parties. Parties to a contract typically have better knowledge of their specific circumstances, the relevant local business conditions, and their own subjective preferences and valuations, than judges and legal scholars do. Thus, it is better if the parties themselves work out the terms, and if sophisticated parties are incentivized to discuss and raise the relevant issues with unsophisticated parties, which Barnett’s conception of default rules encourages.        
            
           In property law, the best default rule is a simple one: if parties do not mutually agree upon a transfer of property, than legal recognition will remain with the original holder of the property. If parties do not like this, than they can manifest their mutual agreement to transfer property clearly.
            
           When it comes to the promissory contracts of contract law, default rules can get more complicated. One question addressed by such default rules is: what damages or remedies are the victims of a breach entitled to from the breacher, in case of breach of contract? This is a contingency that could well be addressed in the original contract. Some contracts even specify precise sums of money to be transferred to victims in case of breach. These are known as ‘liquidated damages clauses’. But what if the original contract does not specify what damages are to be paid in case of breach of contract? In this case, the legal system must follow the default rule that it has decided upon. Here, I think the best default rule is: specific performance in most cases, but if not feasible, than expectation damages. Specific performance is a remedy for breach of contract that basically does not allow people to breach their contracts. If someone seeks to breach, the court forces them to deliver what they promised. However, as part of the default rule, if the party in breach can show that specific performance is unreasonably onerous, than expectation damages could be awarded instead. Expectation damages are a sum of money that is calculated with the goal of putting the victim of the breach in the same position as they would have been had the contract been specifically performed. These calculations can often be quite uncertain, and often tend towards undercompensation for the breach, which is why specific performance should be the presumptive form of relief in the default rule.

This default rule is one that unsophisticated parties would expect. Unsophisticated parties generally think that if you execute a legally binding contract with someone, they are seriously bound to do what they promised for you. If this proves overly difficult given changed circumstances, than it is not a giant leap to translate this expectation into a money sum of damages. If the parties to the contract think that this simple measure of damages is unreasonably onerous for the breacher, they can always choose to contract around it, as long as both parties agree to do so.    
            
           Another issue in promissory contracts addressed by default rules is: when is a promise legally enforceable? Courts and contracts scholars have come up with all kinds of sophisticated doctrines to answer this question, involving ‘consideration’, ‘bargaining’, ‘promissory estoppel’, and the like. But at the end of the day, these should just be considered default rules. If parties, on a written and signed contract, write: ‘We, the undersigned, agree that this agreement is intended to be legally binding’, than that should settle the issue, without recourse to any of the doctrines above.  
            
           Another issue is: what does it take for a breach of contract to occur? Does a minor breach of a relatively minor clause in the contract invalidate the whole thing? The best default rule is that if the breaching party shows a genuine willingness and ability to address this breach and to prevent more breaches from happening in the future, than the breach is not ‘material’, and the contract is not invalidated by it[4]. If not, than the breach is ‘material’, and the contract is invalidated. This is a default rule because the parties could well stipulate in the original contract that any minor breach of any clause in the agreement constitutes a full breach. For projects requiring great attention to detail and precision, this stipulation might make sense for the parties. Alternatively, the parties could stipulate that only ‘gross’ breaches will invalidate the contract, but that the party in less than gross breach has a duty to rectify such breaches and perhaps to pay specified money penalties to the other party for any such breach.
           
           How about for tort law, an area where the concept of default rules is not typically seen to apply? I maintain that much of tort law is a series of default rules because parties should have the legal right to waive some of the ‘default’ liability through contractual waiver agreements. Given this ability, I think that the best tort law default rule is the strict liability rule. This rule states that if a party can be shown to have caused harm to the person or property of another, that person is fully liable for that harm, to the extent of his role in the causation of that harm. The major competitor of this rule is the negligence rule, which says that people are only liable for harm caused to others if they have not taken ‘reasonable’ precautions against inflicting such harm.

Whatever one may think of the substantive merits of these two rules, when considered as a default rule that should be based on the common sense expectations of unsophisticated parties, the strict liability rule clearly wins. If you cause harm to my person or property, you are responsible for recompensing me for that harm. I think that this simple and straightforward rule is the one that unsophisticated parties would generally expect to prevail. This is especially true given how hard it is for courts to define what a ‘reasonable’ precaution is, and thus to define what ‘negligence’ is. Unsophisticated parties generally don’t expect the law to be so uncertain and malleable, and even if they did they still wouldn’t really know what exactly to expect in specific circumstances. Also, for most business-customer relationships especially, the more likely potential tortfeasor tends to be the more sophisticated party (the business selling goods or services) than the potential victim (the customer). Strict liability is the most onerous default rule for the sophisticated potential tortfeasor, so they will be incentivized to communicate with and work out an alternative arrangement with the potential victim before entering into a business relationship with them.  This process of information sharing, bargaining, and eventual mutual agreement will often result in a more mutually beneficial arrangement of liability than one imposed by the courts from on high.

For example, imagine that the owner of a private playground specifies that everyone who pays for their children to use the playground must agree that the playground owner will not be liable if the child hurts themselves on the playground, unless there is something truly negligently unsafe about it such as exposed rusty nails or exposed asbestos. This arrangement will result in the relevant liability rights being modified in a way that facilitates both parties taking reasonable, not so costly precautions. The parents can drill some basic safety tips into the heads of their children, while the playground owner can make sure that the playground is free of rusty nails and asbestos. This situation is better than if the playground owner were fully liable, and had to coat everything with cushions to guard against children hurting themselves, or if the playground owner was completely free of liability, in which case rusty nails and asbestos could abound.

Thus, it is not so much that strict liability is a good rule in all, or even most, circumstances. It is that strict liability is a good default rule that incentivizes parties to work out more mutually beneficial liability arrangements for themselves.  

The final thing that ‘law imposed from on high’ must see to is: maintaining the legal apparatus itself. We have given tasks to ‘law imposed from on high’, and we have assumed that the legal system will have an enforcement arm that can enforce both the ‘laws imposed from on high’ and the private, legally binding agreements of contracting parties. This obviously requires personnel and resources to execute. Under the anarchist ideal, providers of legal services would be able to maintain themselves based on voluntary subscriptions paid by the users of their legal services. However, if one suspects that this system would soon lead to warlordism and chaos, as I do, than the legal system must impose a ‘law from on high’ that allows it to fund itself non-voluntarily. Here is where taxation law comes in. The monopolistic legal system of a given geographical area levies mandatory contributions from the inhabitants of that area, according to various principles and rules of taxation.     

So there you have it, ‘law imposed from on high’ is necessary to deal with the issues of: 1. The assignment of initial property rights. 2. Determining when a contract exists and interpreting its meaning. 3. Determining when an injury or trespass is ‘caused’ by another person or not. 4. Setting Default Rules. 5. Maintaining the legal apparatus. This done, the system of free contract can deal with most of the rest of society’s legal issues in a voluntary, decentralized, and mutually beneficial fashion. People can set and alter their legal relations with one another through the mechanism of free contract, and create rules of law that best serve their individual purposes. This empowering phenomenon allows people to take charge of a significant portion of their own legal destinies, instead of leaving it all up to judges and legislators to decide and to impose on us. All of this is what the Mighty Contract allows.     

                   
                           







[1] Lon Fuller, ‘Consideration and Form’, 806-807.
[2] Randy Barnett, “Contract Is Not Promise; Contract Is Consent”, 660.
[3] Randy Barnett, ‘Contract Is Not Promise, Contract Is Consent’, 661.
[4] Randy Barnett, Contracts, Chapter 5: Performance.

No comments:

Post a Comment