Monday 1 April 2013

Dynamic Versus Static Political Ideals



            Any normative political theorist must have some kind of political ideal in mind when he criticizes the status quo or suggests reforms. This ideal must ultimately be based on one of three overarching political principles, and then qualifications or amendments are then added. These three basic principles are: freedom, elitism, or egalitarianism.
            
           The holder of the political principle of freedom maintains that in most cases, individuals, by pursuing their own ends, and exchanging and cooperating with one another to pursue those ends, spontaneously generate a good social order. Each individual owns themselves and the fruits of their labour or goods received through the voluntary exchanges that they make, hence the institution of private property. The free-market is seen as economically preferable to socialism, and hence most government interventions with the free-market order are seen as counter-productive. Furthermore, individuals are seen as their own ends, not just means to some ‘collective’ end, and hence the individual freedom to pursue individually chosen ends is considered as a vital good to be pursued in its own right.
            
           The holder of the political principle of elitism maintains that some individuals, by some kind of alleged superiority, whether it is strength, intelligence, race, birth, or anything else, should have special privileges that other individuals do not. Because of their superiority, these individuals are allowed to rule over the ‘inferior’ individuals, whether for their alleged own good or for the good of the ruling class, whose interests are deemed more important. 
            
           The holder of the political principle of egalitarianism maintains that the mere fact of being born entitles the individual to material equality with the rest of humanity. Individuals do not own themselves, each individual is owned by all other individuals. If someone accumulates more material wealth than the rest of his fellow humans, the surplus should be confiscated and distributed equally amongst all others.
            
           A static political ideal is the ideal political arrangement of a thinker, which would be realized if he became an omnipotent dictator with the power of changing political arrangements instantaneously. Usually, these political ideals will be an eclectic mixture of the three ‘extremist’ political principles enumerated above. The mere fact that the thinker has a concrete political ideal (a set of things that governments should be doing) usually makes him a bit of an elitist. The whole exercise assumes that the thinker, and those who think like him, know what is better for their fellow men more than they themselves do through their voluntary actions, or else political action, ie. coercion, would not be necessary to achieve the outcome. The egalitarian or elitist side comes out whenever the thinker suggests that resources be taken from one group in order to benefit a group that ‘needs it more’. If for instance, the thinker believes the government should fund the arts, this is an elitist policy because he implies that the tastes of certain people, ie. those who appreciate the arts, are more important than those who do not, and these ‘superior’ people should have the privilege of subsidizing their activities through the forced contributions of those ‘inferior’ people who do not see the value of the arts. If the thinker believes that the government should take from richer citizens in order to help out poorer citizens, this is the egalitarian side. But, unless the political ideal is a completely totalitarian socialist dictatorship, the freedom principle is still present in the political ideal.
            
           Allow me to lay out my static political ideal as an example. In most things, I am a libertarian and adhere to the freedom principle. I think that due to the subjectivism of tastes and the elegance and effectiveness of the free-market mechanism in generating material prosperity, freedom is the most effective way of satisfying the most people’s desires. However, I am not an anarchist but a minarchist, I believe in a minimal role for government, the social mechanism of coercion and compulsion. I suspect, though I do not know for sure, that a minimal, democratic government, coercing people for funds in order to provide their monopolistic law and security functions, would mean less coercion than anarchism, where everyone is free to organize themselves into a defence (or offence!) agency and collect funds from willing contributors. I suspect that some of these agencies might become aggressive and try to enrich themselves through coercion like bandits. Also, without a monopoly of law, there could be many different variants of law, not all of which would accord with individual freedom (shari’a law for example), and there would be no monopolistic agency powerful enough to ensure that individual freedom was always respected. Thus, I estimate, though I have no concrete proof, that the public coercion of a consistent minarchism would be less than the private coercion of anarchism.
            
           Moving on to other deviations from the freedom principle, in order to appease bleeding hearts, to prevent people from citing ‘necessity’ as an excuse for breaking the law, and to give people a basic guarantee that his fellow men will not let him die due to poverty, I would allow for a very minimal social safety net for those who simply could not make it in the market economy and whom private charity had not provided for. Another deviation: in order to keep spendthrift people from abusing this social safety net, and in order to ensure that the capital supply necessary for economic growth does not fall too low, I would institute a modest forced savings plan, where individuals would have to set aside, say, 10% of their income as savings, to be invested as they want but to be spent only for medical emergencies, educational investments, or for retirement. Also, in order to ensure that costly, but very valuable, technological innovation continues, I would allow for an intellectual property system of patents and copyrights, with a modest length so as not to stultify innovation and cripple the economy with monopolies, to help actors reap more of the, otherwise external, benefits of technological innovation. Also, if significant global warming and the carbon emissions necessary for it to create serious consequences could be proven in a court of law, I would allow some kind of governmental carbon cap-and-trade system in order to internalize this negative externality. Finally, for my proposed air quality associations, water system associations, and road owner associations who would own these resources, some minimal governmental functions and different property rules may have to be assigned to them.
            
            The static political ideal outlined above is much closer to the pure principle of freedom than those of non-libertarian thinkers. Nevertheless, I did borrow from the principles of both egalitarianism and elitism, however modestly. The minimal social safety net is clearly an egalitarian program: individuals, by the mere fact of being born, are being given a privileged claim to the earned resources of others, in this case, the enforceable claim to be given the resources necessary to live without having to work for them. The other deviations from freedom have elitist elements: I, the thinker, think that people want a certain thing that they have not demonstrated on the market that they want (more capital goods, more technology, a certain size and composition of water and road holding entities) and I endorse using coercion in order to divert resources from what they otherwise would have been spent on to these things. That my paternalism is substantially more modest than that of most political thinkers is a question of degree, not principle.
            
           This brings me to why I call it a static political ideal: because it assumes that this political arrangement, regardless of the fundamental political principles underlying it, will remain the same over time. In the real world of politics, this is not the case. For example, rather than abolishing the Poor Law in England in 1832 (an early form of welfarism), the largely free-market economists and policy makers decided to reform it instead, making it more like the minimal social safety net envisioned in my static political ideal above, where instead of being given payments (outdoor relief), welfare recipients would have to live and work in a workhouse under barracks like conditions, so as to make being on welfare uncomfortable and to try to ‘reform’ the people in the workhouse to make them productive citizens. This, because of the dynamic political process, did not last long though. The egalitarian principle underlying the poor law was stretched further and further in this area until Britain was saddled with a bloated welfare state so characteristic of the modern western world. The same can be said of the United States Income tax, adopted in 1913 at a bottom bracket rate of 1%, top bracket rate of 7%, which reached 20% bottom bracket and 91% top bracket in 1954. Certainly those who were debating the income tax in 1913 did not envision it going up to this extent, nor did the framers of the 1832 Poor Law reforms envisage the modern welfare state, nor did the politicians who advocated modest financial help to schools for poor children envisage mandatory, universal public education. The point is that if a principle can justify an intervention of one magnitude, it can usually be stretched to justify an intervention of a higher magnitude as well.
            
           Thus, as contrasted with the static political ideal, there is also the dynamic political ideal. Here, the political thinker must consider the general principles underlying his political ideal, and whether those principles could be used to justify other political arrangements of which he would not approve. In my case, my modest proposals for a deviation from the freedom principle imply that I do not entirely dismiss the egalitarian principle or the elitist principle, so what is to stop other thinkers or political actors from just pushing the latter two principles a bit further? Why not a higher forced savings rate? Why not direct subsidies of technology? Why not take-over investment choices, because short-sighted people might not invest their capital properly? Why don’t we just spend a little bit more on our social safety net to make it a bit more humane?    
            
           In order to signify that I, as a political thinker, am against these extensions, it is possible that as my dynamic political ideal, I may have to just forget about deviations from the freedom principle and just embrace and defend that principle wholeheartedly. For I think that of the pure principles, the freedom principle is far and away the best and leads to prosperity and a dynamic society, whereas the other two lead to slavery, stagnation, and penury. Ludwig von Mises grappled with this issue. He posited that it might not be such a bad thing if the advertising of products whose advertised benefits could not be substantiated by the natural sciences or the consumption of harmful drugs could beneficially be banned. But, in both cases he quickly went on to say that “freedom is indivisible”, and that once the government starts getting in the business of being a truth commission and regulating what people ingest, the extent of the subsequent tyranny that could result would be virtually endless. Largely for this reason, Murray Rothbard and his modern libertarian followers have proclaimed the principle of freedom absolutely, even to the point of advocating for the total elimination of coercive governments, or anarchism. I think, along with Mises though, that a very limited government, bound by strict rules to stick to defending person and property and that alone, and constitutionally bound by revenue caps, could sustain the freedom principle just as well, if not better, than anarchism so I would advocate consistent minarchism of this kind as my dynamic political ideal.
            
           For my part, I think that it is valuable to have both a static and a dynamic political ideal. This allows the political theorist to more effectively isolate the reasons why he advocates certain measures. Thus, when the leftist accuses the libertarian thinker of not caring for the poor, the libertarian thinker, if his static political ideal involves a minimal social safety net, can defend himself with this position, but he can also explain why it is a dangerous principle that, given the history of such things, would probably balloon into some kind of ultra-coercive and redistributionist welfare state.     

No comments:

Post a Comment