Sunday 11 August 2013

Commentary: Albertan Support for Free-Trade in 1911 and 1921 Federal Elections

(Note: Before reading this commentary, I suggest you read the historical essay upon which it is based here: http://thinkingabouthumansociety.blogspot.ca/2013/08/spotlight-albertan-support-for-free.html)


            Though I tried to confine myself to a factual, historical description in my last post, regular readers of this blog will know which ideology for supporting free-trade policies I favor: the classical-liberal one which was stronger before the First World War. I posted this essay I wrote on political ideology issues surrounding the 1911 and 1921 federal elections in Alberta for two reasons.

Firstly, the argument implicitly challenges the viewpoint of many intellectual historians who recognize no fundamental difference between classical-liberal political ideology and social democratic, ‘modern-liberal’, political ideology. Alan Wolfe, a political scientist who wrote a book about Liberalism, argues:

“The idea that liberalism comes in two forms assumes that the most fundamental question facing mankind is how much government intervenes into the economy. To me, perhaps because so little of the means of production lies under my control, this is a remarkably uninteresting subject. I think of the whole question of governmental intervention as a matter of technique. Sometimes the market does pretty well and it pays to rely on it. Sometimes it runs into very rough patches and then you need government to regulate it and correct its course. No matters of deep philosophy or religious meaning are at stake when we discuss such matters. A society simply does what it has to do.
           When instead we do discuss human purpose and the meaning of life, Adam Smith and John Maynard Keynes are on the same side. Both of them possessed an expansive sense of what we are put on this earth to accomplish. Both were on the side of enlightenment. Both were optimists who believed in progress but were dubious about grand schemes that claimed to know all the answers. For Smith, mercantilism was the enemy of human liberty. For Keynes, monopolies were. It makes perfect sense for an eighteenth century thinker to conclude that humanity would flourish under the market. For a twentieth century thinker committed to the same ideal, government was an essential tool to the same end.”[1]
            Now, first of all, the fact that Doctor Wolfe finds the question of government ownership versus private ownership “uninteresting” does not mean it is unimportant. As for governmental intervention being “a matter of technique”, who are the technicians qualified to prescribe whether private ownership or government intervention is best in any particular case if not politicians and social thinkers that subscribe to various political ideologies? Is the answer really so straightforward, and does it really have nothing to do with philosophy and value judgements? Were the differences between East and West Germany, North and South Korea, differentiated primarily by the amount of government intervention in their respective economies, really just “technical” and “uninteresting”, and completely unrelated to “human purposes” and “the meaning of life”?
            The idea that somehow, completely uninfluenced by political ideologies and philosophies, ‘society’s’ will simply ‘do what they have to do’ economically and automatically decide on the optimal amount of economic freedom versus government intervention in every area of human endeavour is simply not true. Contrary to Doctor Wolfe, the answers to such economic questions are vitally important for societal well-being, have very deep philosophical implications (whether you are allowed to pursue your own ends with the resources you own or are forced to pursue the ends determined by political elites with the resources you once owned seems a pretty deep philosophical difference to me), and as such, one’s position on these issues constitutes one of the most substantial aspects of any person’s political ideology.
            Doctor Wolfe’s suggested criteria for being a ‘liberal’ thinker are very vague and relatively all-encompassing. Optimism, belief in progress, belief in ‘enlightenment’, disbelief of ‘grand schemes’ (although one could argue that Keynes’ plan for the government to ‘manage the economy’ was indeed a ‘grand scheme’), there aren’t all that many modern thinkers who wouldn’t match these criteria. The point of distinguishing phenomena in the world, be they physical entities or ideas, is to increase our understanding of the world and the things that make it up. Precise, exclusive definitions are more useful in this regard than vague, all-encompassing ones, and thus Doctor Wolfe’s criteria, I would suggest, does not aid our understanding of different ideologies, but reduces it.
            The argument of my historical essay is a clear anti-thesis to the view of classical versus modern liberalism represented by Doctor Wolfe. I argue not only that classical-liberalism and social-democratic ‘modern’ liberalism represent two different ideological traditions, but that even when the same political measure (in this case freer trade) is supported by two different political movements, one must still examine the respective ideological backgrounds for their support of the measure. When the ideological background has changed, one is no longer dealing with the same political ideology and must recognize that historically in order to achieve a higher level of understanding of the past, even if the two political movements are supporting the same political measure and thus, superficially, seem to share the same political ideology.
            The second reason I wrote about free-trade politics in Alberta in 1911 and 1921 is because the shift in ideological disposition recognized in the essay serves to represent one of the most significant political-ideological shifts in Western world history: the general post-WWI shift away from classical liberalism towards social democratic ideas. Though classical liberalism had been declining in popularity and social democratic ideology gaining in popularity since the late 19th century, WWI was a watershed that dramatically accelerated this process.
            The reasons why WWI contributed to causing this acceleration are undoubtedly numerous and complex. I will here suggest a few: 1. Marxist-inspired writers blamed capitalism for the phenomena of European imperialism, and European imperial ambitions for the First World War, thus discrediting capitalism in the eyes of those who believed this causal chain to be correct. 2. WWI and its aftermath showed rulers and citizens that military might was once again going to play a major role in human affairs, and that nations had to be ‘strong’ and ‘centrally directed’ in order to be able to survive in that climate, which legitimised some interventionist policies in the name of ‘war-preparedness’. 3. The victory of the Bolsheviks in Russia, which the war had made possible, stirred revolutionary hopes in the minds of communists and fears in the minds of anti-communists, which resulted in more frequent and more brutal clashes between these forces in the post-war period. 4. Blame for the war fell, in the eyes of many, especially younger, people, on the shoulders of the ‘old order’ and all that it represented. In the minds of many, classical liberalism and free-market capitalism were part of this old order which had to be reinvented. 5. The unprecedented governmental powers taken on by the governments of the belligerent countries during the war gave rulers and economic elites a taste for expanded political power which inspired them to try to have the government take on more responsibilities during peacetime in the post-war period.
            In any case, this shift was a momentous one, and suggestive evidence for it is presented in my historical essay.
        
                 
           

     





[1] Alan Wolfe, “A False Distinction”, The New Republic, April 13, 2009. http://www.newrepublic.com/blog/alan-wolfe/false-distinction#

No comments:

Post a Comment