15. Identify whether a disagreement is over means or ends:
When two people disagree over the
desirability of a certain measure, there are two potential sources of this
disagreement. The first, which I will call a scientific disagreement, is over
what results can be expected from adopting a certain measure. It is a
disagreement over whether this particular set of means will produce that particular
end or ends, not over the desirability of the ends themselves. The second,
which I will call a valuational disagreement, is over the desirability of the
ends likely to be produced by the measure.
For example, imagine that someone
proposes that the government should take over the grocery industry. What would
a scientific disagreement on this measure look like? Well, an opponent of the
measure might say that, because the government is presumably not driven by the
profit motive once they have taken over the industry, they are not in a
position to use capitalist economic calculation to its fullest, rendering it
much more difficult for them to determine the relative value of their inputs
and outputs in the eyes of the consumer. This, combined with the lack of
competitors pushing the government grocers to serve the consumers better, will
mean that, from the point of view of consumer satisfaction, the government
take-over will be a disaster.
In response, a supporter of the
measure might say (falsely I believe) that since without government control production is anarchic
and not efficient socially, a government take-over of the vital grocery
industry is a must, the industry is simply too important to be left to the
arbitrary whims of individual businessmen. Notice that both debaters have the
same end in mind, in this case, the most efficient system for producing and
distributing groceries. Theirs is a scientific disagreement because one thinks
that the measure is not in fact a means to that end and is in fact directly
contrary to it, while the other thinks that the measure is the most suitable
means for achieving that end. Note that in a scientific disagreement (yes, even
in the social sciences), there is no room for relativism, agreeing to disagree
because of different world-views or ideologies, or compromise, either the means under consideration are likely to produce the end sought or they are not. Perhaps one debater adheres
to a better theory and/or has interpreted the relevant empirical more cogently
than the other, and it is up to the observer to investigate this matter with
his own intellect to decide who is ultimately more convincing.
Now, let us look at what a
valuational disagreement on this measure would look like. In order to better
isolate the two sources of disagreement, let us assume for the moment that both
debaters agree that the government taking over the grocery industry will
significantly reduce the productivity of the grocery industry in the eyes of
the consumers but that it will allow the government to pursue egalitarian
policies with regards to groceries and to assure that everyone will at least
have enough to eat so as not to starve. The two debaters thus agree on the ends
that the measure will produce, but now their disagreement is over which set of
ends outweighs the other.
The opponent of the measure could
argue that productivity in the eyes of the consumer is the most important
measure of policy effectiveness, given that people’s happiness depends on them
being able to fulfil their desires as much as possible, especially in an area
as important as food. He could also argue how the individual’s freedom to
pursue his own ends in the way he sees fit is vitally important as an end in and
of itself. He may dismiss the so-called advantages of the government being able
to pursue egalitarian policies in the grocery industry, because he may be a
believer in meritocracy based on peoples’ ability to serve their fellow man as
an end in and of itself and he may not place much importance, if any, on the
pursuit of the egalitarian ideal.
The supporter of the measure could
argue just the opposite. He could say that once a certain material threshold
has been met, men should not pursue petty material advantages anymore, and that
man’s voracious appetite for more and more material possessions as a consumer
is wholly misguided and should be curbed. People should be satisfied with a
simple, minimalist diet that the government will provide to them equally and
should not indulge in luxurious gluttony. He may say that individual freedom is
not important as an end, only the individual that conforms to some
philosophical ideal can live with dignity. He may be a great believer in the
ideal of egalitarianism, believing that no man should have more material
possessions than any other and that it is a proper use of the government’s
coercive power to enforce this.
The source of this disagreement is
different evaluations of the desirability of the ends that the measure will
likely produce. If the valuation is done thoroughly, remembering of course to
consider the general principles behind the measure and what would happen if
such principles were applied in other situations, then there is no true right
or wrong in a valuational disagreement. The observer must consider carefully
which set of ends he values more highly and make his decision accordingly. It
is important to know what kind of disagreement you are having with another over
a social issue so that you know how to convince them, either by educating them
on the theory that you believe is correct for a scientific disagreement, or by
trying to convince them to change their subjective valuations in the case of a
valuational disagreement.
16. Process: Theory, Predicted Effects, Cost/Benefit List and
Weighting, Position:
When analyzing a social measure,
start with a scientific analysis (determining what ends the measure is likely
to produce). This will require subscribing to a social or economic theory that
is applicable to the measure in question based on the general reasonableness of
that theory (keeping in mind, while doing so, the preceding tips in this
compilation of course). Then, you must apply that theory to the particular
measure to see what its predictions concerning the likely results of adopting
that measure will be. If applicable, some historical or statistical knowledge
relevant to the measure may be useful to back up the theory applied or in order
to predict which, of the possible results that the theory predicts the measure
could bring about, tends to be the most predominant given certain conditions.
Once this is done with a reasonable
amount of thoroughness, draw up a list of all the main results that you think
the measure will bring about. Remember, as per tip #13, that the general
principle behind the measure could be applied in other situations by using the
measure under analysis as a precedent, so this eventuality should be factored
into your results list. Though tempting, do not draw up the results list as a
cost/benefit list at the moment, remember that no one has evaluated these
results subjectively yet.
Once the un-evaluated list has been
drawn up, consult your own subjective valuations of the results and now
organize the list, in a separate location, as a personal cost/benefit list.
Remember, and I can’t stress this enough, that you must also evaluate the
general principle and its other possible applications.
For example, let us take a measure to
ban tobacco smoking completely. Some items on your results list might include:
1. Likely reduction of lung cancer rates. 2. Probable increased black market
and criminal activity around this activity, resulting in more policing and jail
resources being necessary and a partial crowding-out of above-ground,
law-abiding businesses by underground, law-breaking businesses. 3. People
would not waste as much time and money on addictive cigarettes which might allow
them to be more productive and allow them to accumulate more capital. 4.
Restriction of the freedom of individual consumers to fulfil their own
subjectively determined desires in the way that they see fit, resulting in a
reduction of their utility/happiness. 5. Reduction of the chances of aggression
against others via second-hand smoke, which is an invasion of their right to
self-ownership because it forces non-consenting people to inhale potentially
dangerous substances. 6. General principle: the government has a right and a
duty to prevent consumers from using goods that the government considers to be
unhealthy. This measure could be used as a precedent for other measures, such
as banning large soft drinks, banning fatty foods, banning television and video
games, banning alcohol, etc…
The theories that I employed aspects
of to come up with this results list includes: Austrian economic theory,
Libertarian social theory, the medical theory that accepts the empirical
correlation between smoking and lung cancer as causation. As for my
cost/benefit list based on my subjective valuations of the results, I would
place #2, #4, and #6 as costs, #1, #3, and #5 as benefits. I am not done yet
though, as not all costs and benefits are created equal, thus I must compare
the complex of costs versus the complex of benefits and see which course I
prefer. In this case, I think that the costs far outweigh the benefits. The
prohibition era illustrates how effective a spur to the formation of violent
criminal organizations the criminalization of popular substances is, thus #2 is
a serious problem for my own safety and the general moral fabric of society.
Since all values are subjective, who am I to say that people are making the
incorrect choice when they accept an increased risk of lung cancer in exchange
for the satisfaction that they get from smoking? Thus, I think that #4 trumps
#1. But it is #6, the general principle, which really troubles me, for the last
thing I want is a busy body government telling me what I can and cannot do with
my body and my time. Certain lifestyle choices, such as my enjoyment of sweet
Chinese fast food, consumption of large quantities of red meat, and penchant
for staring at screens for the greater part of my time, would perhaps not be considered
optimal by a government commission, but they contribute to making me happy and
thus I choose them even though I know there are certain health implications that come from these choices. As for #3, I don’t
believe I have the right to force people to be more productive as I would not want them to force me to be so. And as for #5,
while this is indeed a serious problem, there are several ways, such as the
designation of certain areas as smoking areas and the treating of people
smoking indoors in the presence of unwilling people or children as aggressors,
prosecutable in the courts, to address this problem without the outright
banning of smoking.
Thus, performing these steps should
allow you to make a personal decision about whether you support a social
measure or not. After this, you may want to try to convince others to come
around to your way of thinking on this issue. For this, I recommend that you
show your un-evaluated results list to the person you are trying to convince
and ask them to make their own cost-benefit list. If they reach a different
result than you, you can then bring up your own cost/benefit list and overall
assessment and engage in a valuational debate to persuade them to see the issues
your way.
Both these tips are excellent.
ReplyDeleteI like the idea of writing down the list, and evaluating it separately.
Also agreeing that we are arguing over methods to achieve a common goal helps to keep the discussion civil!
Yeah, I agree with you that arguments over means to a achieve a common end (scientific disagreements)tend to be more civil, and ultimately more productive, than valuational disagreements over the ends themselves. In practice, I suspect that the bulk of most disagreements is over means, rather than ends to be pursued, as most people tend to be in favour of important ends such as material prosperity and not killing innocent people.
ReplyDelete