11. Competition is not war:
Fuzzy thinkers have a tendency to
confuse the commercial competition of the free-market with violent warfare. However, the
two are completely different. Though sometimes businessmen will advocate for
the use of coercion to advance their interests, this does not mean that
free-market competition as such is the same as violent warfare. Consider a
soccer game. The purpose of the soccer game is to determine which team is
better at playing soccer. There are rules of the game to ensure, as much as possible,
that factors other than the relative soccer-playing abilities of the two teams
do not affect the outcome. Thus, if the players on one team decided to bring
concealed pistols to the game, and went on to massacre the other team in order
to ‘win’ the game, we cannot really talk about a soccer game anymore. The team
with the pistols did not compete with the other team based on their
soccer-playing abilities, but used violence to tilt the outcome in their
favour.
Similar considerations apply to
commercial competition. The purpose of commercial competition is to serve the
consumers in the most economical, high-quality way. In contrast to soccer, this
competition is not just to determine who is the ‘best’ at business, but to
ensure that the people who are the best suited to serve the consumers in a
particular way do so, and that others are spurred to surpass the established
providers in consumer satisfaction, which is also a boon to the world’s
consumers. There are rules of commerce to ensure, as much as possible, that
factors other than the relative consumer-serving abilities of the competitors
do not affect the outcome. Thus, if the operatives of one company decided to
steal the products of another company or petitioned the government to prohibit
the other company from competing with them, we cannot really talk about
free-market competition anymore. The company employing coercion did not compete
with other companies based on their ability to serve the consumers, and in
doing so, both the world’s consumers and the potential competitors are injured.
Another spurious argument, which is related to the confusion described above, is to
assert that rich companies and individuals can exert “economic power” over
others, which is just as bad as coercive power. But, it is difficult to see why
wealth equates to coercive power. Everyone in a market society has the right to
either exchange or not exchange with anyone else. If a rich person decides that
he would rather not pay $1000 to a cleaning lady for a day but would rather pay
$200 to the cleaning lady for a day, the cleaning lady has the option of either
accepting the $200 or not accepting it. To take away the “economic power” of
the rich employer, the cleaning lady would have to have the right of forcing
him to make any exchange that she saw fit, in this case perhaps $1000 or more.
Also, the market ensures that the employer could not just pay $1 to the cleaning
lady for a day, because presumably competing employers value her services more
than $1 and would employ her instead, closer to the going market wage for
cleaning ladies of her calibre.
Others say that free-market
economists always go on about the consumers determining the production process,
but not all consumers have an equal voice in determining this, hence the system
is not fair and undemocratic. But the rich having greater relative consumption power is
precisely what incentivizes them to serve the consumers effectively, as discussed in tip #4,
otherwise why would they bother? Voluntary exchange and coercion are completely
different things analytically, and to lump them together is to obfuscate one of
the most important distinctions in the social sciences.
12. Define your terms:
When engaging in argument, about
social issues in particular, it is very important that both participants agree
on the definitions of the terms that they are using. Debates that revolve
around two different definitions of a term are useless. Only when the term
signifies the same thing in both participants’ minds can a proper discussion be
held about the desirability of what that term signifies.
For example, there is a lot of
disagreement over the meaning of the term ‘capitalism’. Marxists will say that
capitalism is a stage of history, and that in this stage, there are various
historical sub-stages of capitalism (early capitalism, late capitalism).
Different economic policies are associated with these sub-stages, for example,
early capitalism favours free-trade policies, while late capitalism favours
protectionist policies. For the free-market economist though, capitalism is
equated with the unhampered market and contrasted with government economic
interventions and socialism, the ultimate government economic intervention.
With this definition, it is absurd to say that protectionism is a late
capitalist policy, by definition protectionism is a government intervention and
hence a deviation from pure capitalism.
It is obvious how frustrating an
argument between two disputants that held these two different definitions of
capitalism would be. If both, for example, thought that protectionism was a bad
thing, but one attributed it to late capitalism and another to government
interventionism and thus not capitalism, then they would not really be
disagreeing with one another, only wasting their time with definitional
debating.
As another example, the word liberty
is subject to an array of different definitions. Some think that liberty means
the freedom to do whatever one wants, regardless of its effects on others.
Thus, the freedom to rob, murder, and assault would be the most consistent
realization of the call for liberty. Libertarians and free-market economists
have a different definition though. For the libertarian Murray Rothbard,
liberty is an outgrowth of the right to self-ownership and the corollary right
to own property that one has created, homesteaded, or been given/sold. Thus,
liberty for him means the respecting of people’s property rights in themselves
and their justly-held material possessions. For free-market economist Ludwig
von Mises, liberty can only exist in society, because it is defined as freedom
from arbitrary interference with your person and property by other members of
society. Thus, in the lawless jungle, there is no such thing as freedom,
because there is no powerful authority to punish those who aggress against
other people’s persons or property.
Whichever of the latter two
definitions one adopts, it is clear that liberty definitely does not include
the freedom to rob, murder, and assault. Again, a debate about the desirability
of liberty between two disputants with these different definitions of liberty
would be fruitless, because while both presumably agree that a world where everyone
had the freedom to rob, murder, and assault would be bad, they are just arguing
about definitional matters around the term liberty and not making any progress. A
suggestion: if such definitional problems pop up in social controversies, come
up with a new term to signify what you mean. For example, rather than speaking
of capitalism to denote a free-market society, talk about an unhampered
free-market society instead.
No comments:
Post a Comment