13. Always take into account the general principles behind
policies:
When considering a social/economic
policy, don’t just assess it in an intellectual vacuum, in isolation; rather,
assess it also based on the general rule or principle underlying it. For example, imagine
that there is a rich man who is very unpleasant, not a criminal, but very
unpleasant: rude, selfish, obnoxious, narrow-minded. Living in the same city is
a poor man who is very pleasant: polite, concerned for others, charming, and
broad-minded. Seeing this, imagine a pundit proposes that the city’s government
should take half of the rich man’s assets and give them to the poor man, as by
doing so a pleasant person could be enriched at the expense of an unpleasant
person, surely a social gain! A social thinker considering this in isolation
might say: sure, why not? The pleasant person would probably make better use of
his money and besides, he ‘deserves’ it more than the unpleasant person.
If we stop and consider the principle
underlying this kind of policy though, we may have second thoughts. In this
case, the principle is this: any time a democratically elected municipal
government deems a rich man unpleasant and a poor man pleasant, it may step in
and confiscate some of the rich man’s wealth to give to the poor man. But this
is a terrible principle for a number of reasons. First, what criteria does the
government have for distinguishing between unpleasant and pleasant people?
What’s to prevent the government from abusing its power and just arbitrarily
grabbing people’s money to reward its supporters? Second, how about the very
foundation of prosperity and freedom in society: the right to hold property
that cannot be confiscated unless its holder has invaded the personal or
property rights of someone else? Who will bother accumulating wealth and
property by serving the consumers if they can just lose it all at the arbitrary
whim of a judgemental government? Thus, a policy that, taken alone may seem alright,
when probed for the basic principle underlying it, turns out to be a terrible
policy.
It is for this reason that Henry
Hazlitt, in his book on ethics, recommends rule utilitarianism over ad hoc
utilitarianism. First, we have a better chance of assessing the utilitarian
effects of a general rule of conduct over ad hoc, single policy decisions.
Second, principles are important for future action and, once a single policy is
recommended by a social thinker, it can be used as a precedent for recommending
other policies that the original social thinker may not sympathize with. You
may protest all you want that it was not your intent to install a general
principle but merely to recommend the one policy, but the fact is that ideas
take on a life of their own and your precedent will be used to justify certain
general principles that you may entirely disagree with.
Let us take another example, this
time a tangible, contemporary one: Mayor Bloomberg of New York’s ban on large
soft drinks for health reasons. Now, even as an isolated, principle-less policy
there are some possible objections, namely, who is Mayor Bloomberg to say that
everyone who willingly purchases a large soft drink, knowing full well the
health consequences of their action, is making a poor decision? Values are
subjective, and if some individuals value the present consumption of a greater
quantity of soft drink over the cost of health risks in the future, who is
Mayor Bloomberg to say that they are wrong, other than by arbitrarily
substituting his own values for those of the individuals in question? Nevertheless,
an argument could still be made for this policy in isolation, most convincingly
along the lines that since the government must in many cases, under the present
institutional arrangements, pay for the healthcare of its citizens, adopting a
not very harmful ban of large soft drinks in order to help improve the health
of its citizens and thus lower the government’s healthcare costs could be
justified. Of course, one could argue that this just proves the cumulative
nature of interventions and that if the government just got out of the
healthcare market (which it should for other reasons anyway), this argument is
of no effect. Let us not use this line of argument for the moment though and
consider the question another way.
What is the principle underlying this
ban of large soft drinks? Essentially, it is that the government has the right
and/or the duty to make sure that citizens live a healthy lifestyle. In this
case though, why stop at banning large soft drinks and narcotics? Why not
prohibit fatty foods, sugary deserts, and salty snacks? In fact, why stop at
prohibition at all? Why not compel people to eat a portion of spinach a day,
take vitamin tablets, and drink cranberry juice? Why not force people to
exercise for at least 30 minutes every day? The answer is because this is
tyrannical and completely disregards the autonomy and subjective value
judgements of individuals, treating them like dependent, childish wards. Ludwig
von Mises, in chapter 15 of Human Action, made a similar argument when he opined that perhaps it would not be
too bad if the state outlawed the advertisement of any product which could not be proven scientifically to do what it claimed to do, ie. cure acne, make ugly
people pretty, etc… But in the end he did not recommend such a policy because
he said that ‘freedom is indivisible’ and that once the government started
getting into the business of being a truth-commission for the claims of private
citizens, why not extend this function to the far more important statements of
political, social, and religious doctrines? Why not outlaw all political
statements that don’t fit into the models of registered government economists
or the accounts of registered government historians, and outlaw all religious
statements that haven’t been proven using the methods of the natural sciences?
In this case, as in the other examples given, the answer is because while the
initial policy considered may not be bad, the underlying principle is monstrous
to most people.
14. Don’t conflate state and society:
Beware when someone says something
like: ‘You did not build your business alone, society helped you all the way
and hence you owe a debt to society. Thus, you should be willing to pay more
taxes’. What is wrong with this statement? The statement conflates the idea of
society and the idea of state. Society is the network of cooperative
relationships between human beings, including the division of labour and
networks of exchange which are known as the market. This kind of society, the
market society, transcends the boundaries of nation-states and encompasses all
humans that engage in exchange transactions with one another, which now means
the vast majority of the world’s population. The state, on the other hand, is
organized coercion that is considered to be legitimate by its subjects.
Currently, different states occupy different geographical areas, and most geographical areas only have one state that is considered legitimate by the
majority of the region’s inhabitants. Thus, while the market society is
characterized by contractual, voluntary relations and an international scale,
regional states are characterized by hegemonic, coercive relations and a
regional scale. It should be clear that these two conceptual entities are not
the same thing.
It should also be clear what the
fallacy of the statement is. Starting with the true assertion that people
cannot build businesses, or do a lot of good things that they currently do,
without society, it moves on to the false assertion that because of this,
individuals should be willing to pay more taxes to the state. This clearly does
not follow because the market society and the state are separate entities.
Perhaps though, the author of the statement just left out or left implicit the
reasoning linking society and the state and that they really mean that the
market society would be impossible without a state. Leaving aside the
anarcho-capitalist arguments that the market society does not need a state to
function well, it is true that many eminent social thinkers, even very
libertarian-leaning ones such as Mises and Hazlitt, do indeed argue that a
state is necessary for the smooth functioning of the market society. After all,
the market society is a voluntaristic society, but if individuals and
organizations are free to organize private armies and use them to aggress
against the person and property of other members of the market society, then
what do we have left of that voluntaristic society? Thus, it is considered by
many thinkers to be the state’s primary function to defend the persons and
property of its citizens against the aggression of domestic and foreign
criminals or rival states. In this limited sense, we may agree that the
existence of a functioning state is a necessary pre-requisite for a prosperous
market society. But in this case, unless all of the government’s resources are
currently devoted to the protection of person and property and the voters still
feel that more protection is needed, the call for a heavier tax burden on
individuals does not follow.
Thus, the author of the statement
must have something else in mind. And indeed, advocates of big government do hold that the
government’s role extends beyond, far beyond, the protection of person and
property. Transportation infrastructure, public utilities, schools, healthcare
institutions, guardianship of natural resources and the water supply, welfare
payments, aggressive military
ventures, prevention of victimless crimes against someone’s sense of morality
(drug laws for example), and many more are considered to be vital functions of
the state, necessary to the functioning of society as a whole. There is a
libertarian and free-market economics literature on why these things are either
not necessary or could be done better and more economically by private enterprise
which we recommend you consult before deeming any of these so-called state
functions vital to the preservation of society as a whole. For now, suffice it
to say that unless it can be demonstrated that the people in question who are
supposed to be grateful to society for their accomplishments (businessmen in
this case) could not possibly have succeeded without the state provisioning one
of the ‘services’, besides defence, that it currently provisions, it is
illegitimate to demand that these people be grateful to the state for something
that society, taken broadly as the world-encompassing market society, really
made possible.
No comments:
Post a Comment